Skip to main content

Full text of "The place of magic in the intellectual history of Europe"

See other formats


Google 



This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 

to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 

to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 

are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other maiginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 

publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing tliis resource, we liave taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 
We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain fivm automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attributionTht GoogXt "watermark" you see on each file is essential for in forming people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liabili^ can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 

at |http: //books .google .com/I 



THE PLACE OF MAGIC 



INTELLECTUftL HISTORY OF EUROPE 



LYNN THORNBrKE, A. M., 

mf'Um* Vnieeriits Felltne in Burop6<tn IlittOrg 



A DISSERTATION 
»OrMmBr> W PARTUL fUIFILMfiMT OF TUK BKJCreEHKNTS 

i-i,, .i>e '.•riii,.h - niK-'iuK or phiu- -t^v 

' lUii-y OF PouTicAL Science 
COI.UHBW UmvERsn-v 



«C^X■ IJotlt 

lOOS 



11 I 



• * 



THE PLACE OF MAGIC 



IN THE 






INTELLECTUAL HISTORY OF EUROPE 



IS 






BY 



V 



ri 
•J 
■>» 

• I 



■■ I 



\\ 



r , 



■I I 

I 



LYNN TjBORNDIKE, A. M., 

Sometime Unieeraity Fellow in European History 



A DISSERTATION 

SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS 
FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY 

IN THE 

Faculty of Political Science 
CoLUMBU University 






• • 



• « 



• * - * • , - . 



,■ 1 _ 
Hi 






•Rcw Korft 

10O6 



vc*»- 



A i€<^ 



unA 



T^^t 



I 



I: 

I! 



* ^ •-•' 



IXSS THOBXDIKE 



• •_ 



• 
• 






• •• 



• • 






TABLE OF CONTENTS 



CHAPTER I 

ILLUSTRATIONS OF BELIEF IN MAGIC IN MEDLEVAL AND IN EARLY 

MODERN TIMES 

PAGE 

General belief in witchcraft, in astrology, and in the existence of 

magicians . . ii 

Even the most educated men believed in astrology 12 

Further illustration of such beliefs among men of learning, and even 

among scientists 13 

Isidore and Bede 14 

Alexander of Neckam 15 

Michael Scot 16 

Roger Bacon 18 

Bacon's acceptance of astrology 18 

Bacon's belief in occult influence 19 

Vincent de Beauvais, Bernard Gordon, Albertus Magnus, Arnald 

of Villanova 19 

Cabalistic doctrines of Renaissance scholars 20 

Jerome Cardan 22 

Paracelsus and Tycho Brahe 22 

Francis Bacon 23 

Summary of these beliefs 23 

Question whether they are all closely connected 24 

Question whether they were regarded by their authors as magic . . 25 

Importance of magic 26 

CHAPTER II 

magic; its origins, and relations to SCIENCE 

Magic once regarded as a reality 27 

Magic praeternatural rather than supernatural o.'j 

Belief in magic perhaps older than belief in divine beings .... 28 

Magic not originally a secret art 28 

5] 5 



6 CONTENTS [6 

PAGE 

Attitude of primitive man towards nature o . . . . 29 

His effort to explain strange phenomena 30 

His belief in lucky things 31 

His desire to know the future 31 

Hence the probable origin of belief in magic 31 

Chief characteristics of magic 32 

Difficulty in defining magic . . • .. . Z7> 

Gradual disappearance of magic before science 34 

Possible union of magic and science 34 

Importance of union of magic and science 35 

Method of treating that theme in this essay . 36 

CHAPTER III 

PLJNY's NATURAL H^STQHY 

i A fitting starting-point for our discussion 37 

I. The. Character of the Work: 

Its extensive treatment of both science and njagic .... 37 
Objections to regarding it as a true picture Qf ancient 

science 38 

Reasons for so regarding it . • 39 

Pliny the Boswell of ancient science - • 40 

Pliny's relation to mediaeval science 41 

II. Pliny* s Discussion of Magic: 

Its significance 41 

Pliny's remarks concerning the history of magic 42 

"Magic" false, according to Pliny . . 42 

** Magic " an obscene and criminal art,. according to Plipy. 44 

III. Illustrations of Pliny's Fundamental Belief in Magic: 

Inconsistency of his declared scepticism 44 

His belief that animals possess magic properties 45 

His belief that plants have similar occult virtues 45 

Strange qualities of minerals 46 

Magical powers of man 47 

Efficacy of magical ceremonial 48 

Pliny's belief, unpiistakable 49 

Though probably limited 49 

Question as to extent of his belief in astrology 50 

His account of the heay.enly bodies 50 

Influence of the stars upon our planet 51 



7] 



CONTENTS 



7 



PAGE 

Influence of the Stars ugon man . 52 

Belief of Pliny in portents 53 

Attitude of Pliny towards various popular superstitious ob- 
servances • • • 53 

Pliny not esoteric 54 

Conclusions to be drawn from the Natural History 54 

CHAPTER IV 

SOME ANTECEDENTS OF THE- BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE ROMAN EMPIRE 

Derivative and cosmopolitan character of intellectual life during the 

imperial peripd 56 

Extent of our discussion of its antecedents 56 

•Question as to freedom of Greek thought from magic ..... 57 

■Some evidence to the contrary 57 

Doctrines of the Stoics favorable to magic • • • 59 

Pjrthagorean theory of numbers 59 

Attitude of Plato towards ** magic," as he understood the word . . 60 

Plato's fantastic view of nature 60 

. Aristotle's accept^ce of astrology . 61 

^^lstot\t' s History of Animals 62 

Cato's De Re Rustica 63 

CHAPTER V 

BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 

: Outline of contents of this chapter . . . • . • . . • • . 65 

I. General Attitude: 

Prejudice against '*n|agic'' and (^rondewnation of Magi . . 65 

Views of AptUc^ius and of PJiilostrajl^s 66 

In reality a widespread belief in magic t^j 

Explanation of jfipparent o{u>.osi.tion to, astrology .. .. ... 68 

Galen 69 

Neo-Platonism . 70 

Philosophy confounded with magic . . 71 

II. Philo of Alexandria and Allegorical Interpretation: 

Question as to connection.9f allegorical interp^eta.tiqn with 

magic ...... .......... . . . . , . . 72 

Historical importance of allegorical interpretation :^d of 

Philo ......;....'. . . . . . .; '.' .... ^2> 

Nature of. Philo* s allegorical interpretation . . ^ . . ^ . , . . 73 

His influence in the Jiliddle Ages ........ . . . . . . 75 



8 CONTENTS [8 

PAGE 

III. Seneca's Problems of Nature and Divination: 

Scientific traits of Seneca 75 

His tendency to be esoteric and mystical • . . 76 

Ground covered by his book 'j'j 

His partial rejection of magic . 'j'j 

His acceptance of divination 78 

His discussion of divination from thunder 79 

IV. Ptolemy's Tetrabiblos and Astrology: 

An illustration of the astrology of the scientist 80 

Ptolemy and his influence 80 

Scientific tone of the preliminary remarks in the Tet- 
rabiblos 81 

An attempt to base astrology upon natural law ..*•.. 82 

Ptolemy* s explanation of the influence of the planets ... 82 

Summary of remaining contents of his first book 83 

Contents of the other three books 83 

V. The Hermetic Books and Occultism: 

Their nature and history, legendary and actual 84 

Their contents 86 

Their importance 87 

CHAPTER VI 

CRITICS OF MAGIC 

Review of the usual attitude towards magic in the Roman Empire. 88 

I. Opponents of Astrology: 

Cicero, Favorinus and Sextus Empiricus ....... 89 

Considerations which discount their scepticism 89 

Inadequacy of their arguments . , 90 

Astrology attacked as being impracticable 91 

General problem of sidereal influence left untouched ... 92 

II. Cicero's Attack upon Divination: 

In a way an attack upon magic as a whole 93 

Form and arrangement of De Divinatione 94 

Its relations to the past and to the future 94 

Appeal of Quintus to antiquity and to tradition 94 

Cicero's reply; condemnation of reliance on tradition ... 95 

Divination declared quite distinct from science 95 

Divination declared quite contrary to the laws of science . 96 

Idea of magical sympathy rejected 97 



9] 



CONTENTS 



9 



PAGE 

Cicero's attitude very unusual for his time 98 

Question as to his consistency 98 

CHAPTER VII 

THE LAST CENTURY OF THE EMPIRE 

Intellectual characteristics of the period 99 

Marcellus of Bordeaux 99 

Ammianus Marcellinus 99 

His description of the state of learning at Alexandria 100 

His justification of divination as a science loi 

His extraordinary misquoting of Cicero 102 

Synesius 103 

His belief that all parts of the universe are in magic sympathy . . 103 

Further instances of his trust in magic 104 

Macrobius 106 

CHAPTER VIII 

Conclusion 108 



CHAPTER I 

IljtUSTRATIONSiOF BEJil^FIN !N^GICjIN 'MPDIJBYAL AND 

.IN EaRI-Y MOD^JIN TiMKS 

.Even sl flight . acquaintance with European history re- 
veals the .existence of . a number of curious . anjl apparently 
.unreasonable beliefs. prevalent throughout a period extend- 
ing from i^arly inediaeval to comparatively recent times. 
^TJiere is the belief in witchcraft, for instance. From the 
canons of synods in the early Middle Ages down to the 
pitiless executions during the witchcraft. delusion, there i3 
abundant evidence of its prominence. It played its part npt 
oply in humble life, but in court iutfigues and in the a.ccusa- 
tiojjs brought ^t state trial§. 

The belief that one's future could be learned by observing 
the stars was equally widespread. Astrologers throve at the 
courts of kings, and sometimes theiradvice was. taken ev«n 
by him whose every act was held to be under special cjivine 
direction. It would be a great mistake to think that the 
astrologer was maintained merely for the a;mu3eni^t, of 
king and court, like the jester. His i utterances were ^ taken 
most seriously, and the principles of his art were so gener- 
ally accepted as to heconje the cprnmonplapesof the tbpugbt 
•^nd ;the conversation of daily Jif^. In .1305, for in- 
stance, when certain cardinals urged Pope Clement V to 
return to Rome, they reminded him that. every planet was 
,ipost powerful in .its owu house. ^ Indeed, ^veu in our 

iH. C. Lea, History of the Inquisitiqnjn the M^ddfe /^geis (188;;), 
II] II 






j" J 






■> ^ . 






' J - 



J - ■' 

^ J a ^ J 



•^ ^ 



12 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [12 

Speech to-day numerous vestiges of the astrological art sur- 
vive.^ 

Moreover, a grander and more imposing witchcraft dis- 
played itself in the stories of the wizard Merlin and in the 
persons of the wicked magicians with whom knights con- 
tended in the pages of mediaeval romance. So strong was 
the tendency to believe in the marvelous, that men of learn- 
ing were often pictured by subsequent tradition, if not by 
contemporary gossip, as mighty necromancers. Even Ger- 
bert, who seems to have done nothing more shocking than 
to write a treatise on the abacus and build a pipe-organ, 
was pictured as running off with a magician's book and 
daughter, hanging tmder bridges between earth and water 
to escape noxious spells, and making compacts with Satan.^ 

The attitude of the average mind as it has just been illus- 
trated was to a large extent characteristic of the best in- 
•'"J structed and most widely read men. The erudite poet Dante 
accepted the influence of the constellations upon human des- 
tiny. Bodin maintained in his Republic — ^perhaps the great- 
est book pn political science written during the sixteenth 



•• ••• 






• ! . 



• • • • • 



• ••. 



c • 



• ••• 



•>• •- 



• vol. iii, p. 437. Mr. Lea's chapter on " Sorcery and the Occult Arts " is 

very interesting and contains much material which it is difl&cult to find 
elsewhere. 

•••* ^ We speak of persons as jovial or saturnine or mercurial in tem- 

perament ; as ill-starred, and so on. 

: 2 The classic on the theme of magic reputations incurred by the 

•••• learned in ancient and mediaeval times is Gabriel Naude's Apologie 

* pour tous les grands personages qui ont esti faussement soupgonnes de 

Magie** Paris, 1625. That such reputations were often unjustly in- 
curred was recognized long ibefore Naude, however. To say nothing 
•:J» now of Apuleius' Apologia, to which we shall refer later, attention may 

..,,* be called to the fact that even William of Malmesbury, while relating 

with apparent credulity the legends in regard to Gerbert, had the grace 
to admit that "the common people often attack the reputation of the 
learned, and accuse any one of dealing with the devil who excels in his 
art." Gesta Re gum Anglorum, book ii, sees. 167, 168. 



• • 

• •••• 

• ••• • 



• 






13] BELIEF IN MAGIC 13 

century — that astrology was very useful in tracing the de- 
velopment of society/ Aquinas, chief of the mediaeval the- 
ologians, accepted astrological theory, except as limited by 
human free will, and further admitted that most men make 
little use of their liberty of action but blindly follow their 
passions, which are governed by the stars. ^ Among other 
great mediaeval churchmen and canonists, d'Ailly and Ger- 
son both believed that God signified important events in 
advance through the stars, and d'Ailly made some astrolog- 
ical predictions himself. Astrology was much taught in the 
mediaeval universities,* and was regarded as the climax of 
mathematics and as an essential part of medicine. 

It is with such beliefs, accepted by educated men and 
forming a part of the learning and science of the times, that 
we are concerned in this essay. First, it is necessary to give 
some further evidence of the nature and of the general ac- 
ceptance of these beliefs. This object will be most quickly 
and effectively secured by a resirme of the views of a few 
of the men most prominent in the intellectual history of the 
past. These men should offer fair, if not flattering, illus- 
trations of the learning and culture of their times. In 
especial we shall notice the curious notions of those who 
wrote on scientific subjects or showed even a considerable 

^ Ripubliqne, book iv, ch. 2, cited by W. E. H. Lecky, History of 
Rationalism (1900), vol. i, p. 28. The chapter upon "Magic and Witch- 
craft " contains considerable material bearing upon our theme. A simi- 
lar attitude to that of Bodin is found in a political treatise of about 
the year 1300, probably written by Pierre du Bois, where an argument 
for the universal rule of a French monarch is based on astrology. N. de 
Wailly, MSmoire sur un opuscule anonyme (Memoires de Tlnstitut Im- 
perial de France), vol. xviii, pt ii, p. 442. 

^ Sumtna Theologica, pars prima, quaest. 115, arts. 3 and 4. 

• For some data on this point see Hastings Rashdall, The Universi- 
ties of Europe in the Middle Ages (1895), vol. i, pp. 240-250; vol. ii, 
pp. 290, 452, 458, 459. 



X 



14 



MAGIC IN WTULLECTUAL HISTORY 



[1-4 



.< 



apt)r(y£tGh toW^iidfe; tHe rtioAetn scientific spirit. TKis we shall 
do partly bi5<:auSe their- writings seem at first thought the 
place where wef should least expect to find such notions, and 
hence furnifeh- striking illustration of' the alhiost universal 
accdptatice of these bdiefs ; partly because, as we shall soon 
fltid' reason to concludCj there is really some connection be- 
tween . such' beliefs atid science: 

The early Middle Ages^ are not distinguished for! the 
prevalence- of education smd of culture in Latin' Christen- 
dom, to= say nothing of profound knowledge or original 
thought in any particular branch of learning: But in such 
learning and science as there was may be found examples of 
the-beliefs which we wish to consider.' We see thcan' in Isi- 
dore of' Seville, whose Etymologies, we may well believe, 
constituted an oft-consulted encyclopedia- in many a monas- 
tic library for several centuries after the seventh, when it- 
appeared. This saint, like almost all gOod' Christians of 
his day, believed that marvels could be effected through 
magic by the aid of demons, although- such resort to eviL 
spirits he could not condemn too strongly.^ But he saw no 
harm in holding that certain stones possess astonishing^ 
powers,? that the dog-star afflicts bodies with disease, and 
that the appearance of a cOmet signifies pestilence, famine 
or war.* He maintained that it was no waste of time to look 
into the meaning of the numbers which occur in the Bible. 
He thought that they might reveal many sacred mysteries.* 

^ Etymologiae, hk. viii,- ch. 9. In Migne's Patrologia Latina, vol. 
Ixxxii. 

^ Ibid,, bk. xvi, passim. 

8 Ibid., bk. iii, ch. 71. He cbndemned astrology, (however. See ibid., 
and bk. iii, ch. 2"/. 

* " Liber Nutneroriim qUl in Satictis Scriptutis Occurunt." (Also in 
Migne, vol. Ixxxiii, col. 179.) "Non est superfluum numerorum causas 
in Scripturis Sanctis attendere. Habfent enim quamdam scietitiae doc- 
trinam plurimaque mystica sacramenta." 



I.g] BELIEF IN MAGIC' 15 

Bcdc expressed similar views in his scientific treatises/ 
Also> if we nmy- regard as his^two little essays about the 
aiitheHticity' of which there is ' some qu^tiori, he ascribed 
such extraordinary influence to the moon as tomaintain that 
the practice of bleeding should ' be r^^lated - by^ its phases, 
arid wrbte-^with ' some hesitati6n lest he shoiild be- accused 
of magic-^— ^n explanation of how to predict coming, disas* 
ters by observing the time and direction of pfeals of thurtdef;^ 
Passing, over several centuries' during^ which judicial 
astrology is very cc«ispieuous in the mathematical treatises 
which formed the grfeater part • of the • scientific literature' of 
the times,* we come at the close of the twelfth century to 
theDe Naturis Rerum of Alexander Nedcam ( i i$yri2iy) . 
Wfe find him ecstatically) musing over the consonance of >v 
celestial harmony and associating . the seven planets with the 
seven ' liberal arts and the seven gifts- of • thef Holy Spirit,* 
as- if • believing .that there is- some occult virtue in that^ rium- 
ber or some potent sympathy between < these material bodies 
and sudi abstractions asbrandies of leSarriing arid genfcfrie 
virtues; Descending from ■ the skies to thirigs' earthly-^the 
transitiori is easy sirice he believes in the influence -saving 
human free will, of the i^arifetson our 16wer creation *^-^he 

'^'Dt NaiUrd Return, ch\ 245 De tempbfum Ratione, ch. 28: The 
scieatific writing of Bede may be found in vol. vi of his works as 
edited by J. A. Giles. London, 1843. 

^ De Tonitruis ad Herefridum, and De MinuHone Sanguinis sive 
Phlehotomia, Many spurious treatises were attribtrted to Bede * but 
there- are some reasons for believing these genuine, / although they are 
not named by Bede in the list of his writings whkh he gives in his 
Ecclesiastical History. Giles included them in his edition after some 
hesitation. 

* For the predominance of astrology in the mathematics of the 9th, 
ibth, nth and 12th centuries, cf, Histoire LittSraire, vol. v, p. 183; 
vi, 9 ; vii, 137 ; ix, 197. 

* De Naturis Rerum, bk. ii, ch. 173, and bk. i, ch. 7. Volume xxxiv of 
The Chronicles and Memorial^' of Great Britain. (The Rolls Series.) 

'^ Ibid., bk. i, ch. 7. 



i6 



MAGIC m INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 



[i6 



tells us that mugwort prevents the traveler from feeling 
fatigue/ and that the Egyptian fig makes the wrinkles of 
old age vanish and can tame the fiercest bulls once they are 
gathered beneath its branches.* He describes fountains 
with properties as marvelous as those of the herb or of the 
tree." He tells of stones which, placed on the head of the 
sleeping wife, provoke confession of marital infidelity,* or 
which, extracted from the crop of a rooster and carried in 
one's mouth, give victory in war." What is more, words 
as well as plants and stones are found by the careful and 
industrious investigator of nature to have great virtue, as 
experiment shows beyond doubt.'* 

Neckam, despite the fact that according to his editor, 
Thomas Wright, he " not infrequently displays a taste for 
experimental science," "^ was, after all, more of a moraliz- 
ing compiler than anything else. But greater men than 
Neckam, men who were interested in learning and science 
for their own sake, men who knew more and wrote more, 
still cherished beliefs of the same sort. There was Michael 
Scot in the early years of the thirteenth century, the won- 
der of the cultured court of Frederick II, perhaps that mon- 
arch's tutor, the " Supreme Master " of Paris, the man 
v^ho helped much to make the treasures of learning amassed 

1 De Naturis Rerum, bk. ii, ch. 63. 

2 Ibid.f bk. ii, ch. 80. 

* Ibid., bk. ii, ch. 3 et seq. 

^ Ibid., bk. ii, ch. 88. In chapter 87 he writes: " Chelidonius autem 
ruf us portantes se gratissimos f acit ; niger vero gestatus optimum finem 
negotiis imponit, et ad iras potentium sedandas idoneus est." 

'^ Ibid,^ bk. ii, ch. 89. 

^ Ibid., bk. ii, ch. 85. "In verbis et herbis et lapidibus multam esse 
virtutem compertum est a diligentibus naturarum investigatoribus. Cer- 
tissimum autem experimentum fidem dicto nostro facit." 

■^ Preface, p. xii in vol. xxxiv of the Rolls Series. 



17] BELIEF IN MAGIC 1 7 

by the Arabs in Spain the common property of Latin Chris- 
tendom, the introducer to Western Europe of a Latin ver- 
sion of Averroes and of an enlarged Aristotle/ Scot com- 
posed a primer of astrology for young scholars. His writ- 
ings on alchemy show that he experimented in it not a 
little. His Physionomia accepts the doctrine of signatures, 
tells us that these signs on the outward body of the soul's 
inner state are often discovered through dreams, and con- 
tains a chapter giving an extended description of the rules 
of augury — an art on which the author, though a Christian, 
apparently bestowed his sanction. Prophetic verses fore- 
telling the fate of several Italian cities have come down to 
us under his name. A poem of Henri d'Avranches, written 
in 1235-6, recalls to mind the fact that certain prophecies 
concerning the emperor had been made by the then deceased 
Michael Scot, whom the poet proceeds to call a scrutinizer 
of the stars, an augur, a soothsayer, a veridicus vates, and 
a second Apollo.^ A most interesting recipe for invoking 
demons to instruct one in liberal arts is attributed to 
Michael Scot in a manuscript collection of Occulta in the 
Laurentian library. * 

1 My information concerning Michael Scot is mainly derived from 
his biography (Edinburgh, 1897) by Rev. J. Wood Brown, who has 
studied the manuscript copies of Scofs works in various European 
libraries and has succeeded in dispelling much of the uncertainty which 
previously existed concerning the events of Scot's career and even the 
dates of his life. Of Scot's works the Physionomia exists in printed 
form; indeed, eighteen editions of it are said to have been issued be- 
tween the years 1477 and 1660. 

2 The poem is printed in Forschungen zur Deutschen Geschichte, 
vol. xviii, (1878) p. 486. 

• The part of the manuscript containing the experiment was written 
between 1450 and 1500, Brown thinks, but purports to be a copy " from 
a very ancient work.'' If spurious, its fabricator at least shows con- 
siderable familiarity with Scot's life. See Brown, pp. 18-19. The re- 
cipe is given in full in the appendix of Brown's book. 



i8 



MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 



[i8 



Later in the same century stands forth the famous figure 
of Roger Bacon, the stout defender of mathematics and 
physics against scholasticism. Some have ascribed to him 
numerous important innovations in the reahn of natural 
science and of the mechanical arts, and have regarded his 
promulgation of the experimental method, guided by the 
mathematical method, as the first herald note of that modern 
science which was not destined really to appear for yet sev- 
eral centuries. Yet he held that the alchemist, if given 
sufficient time and money, could discover a way not only to 
meet the state's expenses by converting baser metals into 
gold, but also to prolong human existence beyond that limit 
to which it can be drawn out by nature.^ Indeed these ob- 
jects constituted two of the three examples he gave of the 
great advantages to be gained from the pursuit of that ex- 
perimental science which was to disprove and blot out all 
magical nonsense.^ 

How far Bacon let the principles of astrology carry him 
a citation or two will show. That a woman had succeeded 
in living twenty years without eating was, he explained, no 
miracle, but due to the fact that during that period some 
constellation was able to reduce the concourse of the four 
elements in her body to a greater degree of harmony than 
they usually attain. * Nor is it health alone that the stars 
control; they affect human character.* They implant in the 
babe at birth good or evil dispositions, great or small tal- 



1 De Secretis Operibus Artis et Naturae et de Nullitate Magiae, ch. 7. 
Contained in the Appendix of vol. xv of the Rolls Series, edited by 
J. S. Brewer, London, 1859. 

2 Opus Maius, vol. ii, pp. 204-221. Edited by J. H. Bridges, Oxford, 
1897-1900. On page 210 et seq. Bacon gives an elaborate recipe for an 
elixir vitae. 

* Opus Minus, Rolls Series, vol. xv, pp. 373-4. 

* Bridges, Opus Maius, vol. i, pp. 137-139. 



iq] belief in magic 19 

ents. Human free will may either better these innate ten- 
dencies through God's grace or modify them for the worse 
by yielding to Satan's temptings; but in general the stars 
so far prevail that there are different laws and customs and 
national traits under different quarters of the heavens/ 
Nay more, astrology offers proof of the superiority of Chris- 
tianity to other religions and gives insight into the nature 
of Antichrist.^ 

As one might surmise from Bacon's belief in the potent 
effect of sidereal emanations, he makes much of the theory 
that every agent sends forth its own virtue and species into 
external matter. This leads him to accept fascination as a 
fact. Just as Aristotle tells that in some localities mares 
become pregnant by the mere odor of the stallions, and as 
Pliny relates that the basilisk kills by a glance, so the witch 
by the vapor from her bleary eye draws her victims on to 
destruction. In short, "Man can project virtue and species 
outside himself, the more since he is nobler than all corporeal 
things, and especially because of the virtue of the rational 
soul." * Hence the great effects possible from spoken words 
or written characters ; although one must beware of falling 
into the absurdities and abominations of the magicians. 
Bacon, moreover, was like Scot a believer in the doctrine 
of signatures.* 

Other men of the same period prominent in science who 
held similar beliefs we can scarcely stop to mention. There 
was Vincent de Beauvais, the great encyclopedist, and Ber- 

^ Compendium Studii, Rolls Series, vol. xv, pp. 421-422. 
2 Bridges, Opus Maius, vol. i, pp. 253-269. 

* De SecretiSy ch. 3, discusses this question of fascination and also the 
power of words and of the human soul. In regard to characters and 
incantations, see De Secretis, ch. 2, and the Opus Tertium, which is also 
contained in vol. xv of the Rolls Series, ch. 26. 

* Opus Tertium, ch. 27, 



20 



MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 



[20 



nard Gordon, a physician of Montpellier and a medical 
writer of consideraible note, who nevertheless recommended 
the use of a magic formula for the treatment of epilepsy.^ 
There was Albertus Magnus with his trust in such wonder- 
ful powers of stones as to cure ulcers, counteract potions, 
conciliate human hearts, and win battles; and his theory 
that ligatures and suspensions, and gems carved with proper 
images possess similar strange virtues.^ There was Arnald 
of Villanova who propounded such admirable doctrines as 
that a physician ought first of all to understand the chief 
functions of life and chief organs of the body and that the 
science of particular things is the foundation of all knowl- 
edge, and yet who believed in astrological medicine, wrote 
on oneiromancy and interpreted dreams, translated treatises 
on incantations, ligatures and other magic devices, and com- 
posed a book on the Tetragrammaton or ineffable name of 
Jehovah.* 

That marvelous power of words — especially of the divine 
names of angels and of the Supreme Deity — ^which we may 
suppose Arnald to have touched upon in his Tetragram- 
maton, was discussed at length by a series of scholars at the 
close of the fifteenth and beginning of the sixteenth century 
whose names are most familiar to the student of those 
times. These men pushed the practice of allegorical inter- 
pretation of sacred writings, which had been in constant 
vogue among religious and theological writers from the days 

^ " Caspar fert myrram, thus Melchoir, Balthasar aurum. 
Haec tria qui secum portabit nomina regum 
Solvitur a morbo Christi pietate caduco." 

Hist, Litt, val. xxv, p. 327. 
2 See Liber Mineralium. Opera Omnia, ed. Borgnet (1890), vol. v, 
page 23 et seq. 

* Two good accounts of Arnald are those in the Histoire Litteraire, 
vol. xxviii and Lea, History of the Inquisition, vol. iii, pp. 52-57. Older 
accounts are generally very misleading. 



2 1 ] BELIEF IN MAGIC 2 1 

of the early Christian Fathers, to the extreme of discover- 
ing sublime secrets not only by regarding every incident 
and object in Scripture as a parable, but by treating the 
text itself as a cryptogram. Not only, like Isidore, did they 
see in every numerical measurement in the Bible mystic 
meaning, but in the very letters they doubted not there was 
hidden that knowledge by which one might gain control of 
all the processes of the universe; nay, penetrate through 
the ten sephiroth to the unspeakable and infinite source of 
all. For our visible universe is but the reflected image of 
an invisible, and each has subtle and practically unlimited 
power over the other. The key to that power is words. 
Such were the doctrines held by Pico Delia Mirandola 
(1463-1494) who asserted that no science gave surer proof 
of Christ's divinity than magical and cabalistic science ; ^ 
such were the doctrines of the renowned humanist, John 
Reuchlin, who^connected letters in the sacred text with in- 
dividual angels; ^ of Henry Cornelius Agrippa (i486- 1535) 
who, inspired by Reuchlin's De verbe mirifico and De arte 
cabalistica, declared that whoever knew the true pronuncia- 
tion of the name Jehovah had " the world in his mouth ;" * 
of Trithemius from whom Paracelsus is said to have ac- 
quired the " Cabala of the spiritual, astral and material 
worlds.'' * 

Moreover, the writings of men primarily devoted to 
science continued through the sixteenth and on into the 

^ J. M. Rigg, Giovanni Pico Delia Mirandola, London, 1890, pp. viii-x. 

2 Janssen, History of the German People, vol. iii, p. 45, of the English 
translation by A. M. Christie (1900). 

•Henry Morley, Life of Agrippa von Nettesheim (London, 1856), 
vol, i, p. 79. This biography includes a full and instructive outlmc 
of Agrippa's work on Occult Philosophy. 

* A. E. Waite, Hermetical and Alchemistical Writings of Paracelsus, 
vol, i, p. xii. 



22 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [22 

seventeenth century to contain much the same occult the- 
ories that Michael Scot, Roger Bacon and Albertus Magnus 
had accepted and discussed. Jerome Cardan, one of the 
most prominent men of his time in mathematics and medi- 
cine — indeed, the discoverer of new processes in the former 
science — nevertheless believed in a strong attraction and 
sympathy between the heavenly bodies and our own, cast 
horoscopes and wrote on judicial astrology. In his Arith- 
metic he treated of the marvelous properties of certain 
numbers ; in other writings he credulously discussed demons, 
ghosts, incantations, divination and chiromancy. His thir- 
teen books on metoposcopy explain how to tell a person's 
character, ability and destiny by a minute examination of 
the lines on different portions of the body and by warts. 
He owned a selenite which he believed prevented sleep and 
a jacinth to which he attributed an opposite influence.^ 

The vagaries of Paracelsus are notorious, and yet he was 
far more than a mere quack. Tycho Brahe (i 546-1 601) 
was a faithful follower of experimental method. He saw 
that the science of the stars could amount to little imless 
based on a mass of correct observations, and was one of 
the first to devote his life to that foundation of patient and 
systematic drudger)'^ on which the great structure of modem 
science is being reared. His painstaking endeavor to have 
accurate instruments and his care to make allowance for 
possible error were the marks, rare enough in those days, 
of the true scientist. Yet he made many an astrological 
prognostication, and was, as his biographer puts it, " a 
perfect son of the sixteenth century, believing the imi~ 
verse to be woven together by mysterious connecting- 
threads which the aKitanplation of the stars or of the 

^ For Cardan, sec the biography in two volumes by Henry Morley, 
London, 1854, and that in one volmne by W. G. Waters^ London. 1898L 



23] BELIEF IN MAGIC 23 

dements of nature might unravel, and thereby lift the veil 
of the future.*' ^ He also dabbled in alchemy, believed in 
relations of occult sympathy between "the ethereal and 
elementary worlds," and filled his mind with the teachings 
of Hermes Trismegistus, Geber, Arnald of Villanova, Ray- 
mond Lullius, Roger Bacon, Albertus Magnus, and Para- 
celsus. 

Finally, even Francis Bacon, famed as the draughtsman 
of the chart which henceforth guided explorers in the 
domain of science, thought that there was considerable value 
in physiognomy and the interpretation of natural dreams, 
though the superstition and phantasies of later ages had 
debased those subjects;^ and in divination if not "con- . 
ducted by blind authority." * He said that by a reformed / 
astrology one might predict plagues, famines, wars, sedi- 
tions, sects, great human migrations and " all great dis- 
turbances or innovations in both natural and civil affairs." * 

Such are the beliefs which for a long time pervaded the 
thought and learning of Europe; beliefs of the widespread 
acceptance of which we have noted but a few striking illus- 
trations. They constitute a varied and formidable class of 
convictions. There was the notion that from such things 
as the marks upon one's body, or from one's dreams, or 
from peals of thunder, flight of birds, entrails of sacrificial 
victims and the movements of the stars, we can foretell the 
future. There was the assumption that certain precious 
stones, certain plants and trees and fountains, certain ani- 
mals or parts of animals have strange and wonderful vir- 
tues. There was the idea that man, too, possesses marvd- 

^J. L. R Dreyer, Tycho Brake. A Picture of ScienMc Life and 
Work in the Sixteenth Century (Edinburg'h, 1890), p. 56. A valu- 
able book. 

2 De Augtnentis Scientiarum, bk. iv, ch. i. 

• Ibid., bk. iv, ch. 3. * Ibid, bk. iii, oh. 4. 



24 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [24 

ous powers to the extent that he can fascinate and bewitch 
his fellows. Nor should we forget the attribution to the 
heavenly bodies of an enormous influence over minerals 
and vegetation, over human health and character, over 
national constitutions and customs, even over religious 
movements. We find this notion of occult virtue extended 
to things without physical reality: to words, to numbers, 
to written characters and formulae. It is applied to certain 
actions and ways of doing things : to " ligatures and sus- 
pensions," for instance. Then there was the belief that 
wonders may be wrought by the aid of demons, and that 
incantations, suffumigations, and the like are of great value 
in invoking spirits. Finally, there was a vague general 
notion that not only are the ethereal and elementary worlds 
joined by occult sympathy, but that all parts of the universe 
are somehow mystically connected, and that perhaps a single 
magic key may be discovered by which we may become 
masters of the entire universe. 

How shall we classify these beliefs ? What shall we call 
them? What is their meaning, what their origin and 
cause? As for classification, it is easy to suggest names 
which partially apply to some of these notions, or ade- 
quately characterize them individually. The art of signa- 
tures, oneiromancy, augury, divination, astrology, alchemy, 
the Cabala, sorcery, and necromancy are some designations 
which at once come to mind. But no one of them is at all 
adequate as a class name for all these beliefs and the prac- 
tices which they involve, taken together. Are not these 
notions, nevertheless, closely allied; is there not an inti- 
mate relation between them all ? And is not " magic " a 
term which will include them all and denote the general 
subject, the philosophy and the art, of which they all are 
branches ? 

True, many of the holders of the beliefs above enumer- 



25] BELIEF IN MAGIC 25 

ated declaimed against " magic." ^ But sometimes fear of 
being accused of magic was their very reason for so doing. 
Bede had such a fear when he treated of divination by- 
thunder. Roger Bacon took suspicious care to insist that 
his theories had nothing to do with magic, which he de- 
clared was for the most part a mere pretense and could 
bring marvels to pass only by diabolical assistance.^ The 
writer of the Speculum Astronomiae — ^probably Albertus 
Magnus — found it necessary to write a treatise to distin- 
guish books of necromancy from works on "astronomy," 
i. e,y astrology.^ Coming to a later age, we find Agrippa 
frankly owning his trust in magic, and including under it, 
in his three books of Occult Philosophy , practically all the 
beliefs that we have mentioned. For him magic embraced 
the fields of nature, mathematics and theology. Indeed, 
men of his day and of the century following displayed a 
tendency to stretch the term to include true science. He 
himself called magic " the acme of all philosophy." Gio- 
vanni Battista della Porta (i 540-161 5), not it is true with- 
out considerable justification, called his encyclopedic work on 

1 Bodin for instance condemned " magic " m his De Magorum Dae- 
monomania (Paris, 1581). 

2 Bridges, Opus Maius, vol. i, p. 241. See too the De Secretis Operi- 
bus Artis et Naturae et de Nullitate Magiae. Rolls Series, vol. xv, 
appendix. 

* Spec. Astron.f ch. 17. Albertus Magnus, Opera Omnia, ed. Borgnet 
(1890), vol. X, pp. 629 et seq. And he finally came to the conclusion 
that " concerning books of necromancy the better judgment — ^prejudice 
aside — seems to be that they ought rather to be preserved than de- 
stroyed. For the time is perchance near at hand in which, for reasons 
which I now suppress, it will be advantageous to consult them occasion- 
ally. Nevertheless, let their inspectors abstain from abuse of them." 
Ch. 17. 

Similarly Roger Bacon, in his De Secretis, ch. 3, after mentioning 
books of magic to be eschewed, remarked that many books classed as 
magic were not such buit contained worthy wisdom. 



26 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [^S 

nature Natural Magic .^ Lord Bacon chose to understand 
magic " in its ancient and honorable significance " among* 
the Persians as " a sublimer wisdcwtn or a knowledge of 
universal nature." •He said that as physics, investigating* 
efficient and material causes, produced mechanics, so meta- 
physics, studying into forms, produced magic* 

Apparently, then, magic has a broad significance and a 
long history. The word itself takes us back to the Magi 
of ancient Persia; the thing it represents is older yet. It 
will form the theme of our next chapter, where we shall 
discuss its history and its meaning, and then the partic- 
ular significance of those beliefs accepted by men of learn- 
ing which have been enumerated in the present chapter. 

* Magiae Naturalis Libri XX. Lyons, 1651. 

* De Augmentis, bk. iii, ch. 4. 



CHAPTER II 

Magic: Its Origins and Relations to Science 

To men of the past — how long ago does not at present 
matter — ^magic meant far more than the performance for 
their amusement of clever tricks, which however puzzling 
they knew well enough were based upon illusion and de- 
ception. There was a real magic for them. 

This faith in the reality of magic was not, moreover, 
merely the outcome of men's belief in the existence of evil 
spirits, in the power of those spirits to work changes in 
matter or to predict the future, and in man's power to guin 
their services. We sometimes speak of magic and necro- 
mancy as if they were identical, and mediaeval writers often 
did the same thing, but such is not the case. If we but con- 
sider the meaning of the word " magic " when used as an 
adjective, we perceive that thus to restrict its scope as a 
noun is incorrect. What is a magic cloak, for instance? 
It is simply a cloak possessing properties which cloaks in 
general do not possess and which we are surprised to find 
in cloaks. Most cloaks keep us warm or improve our per- 
sonal appearance; this cloak makes us invulnerable and in- 
visible. A demon or a fairy may have endowed the cloak 
with these extraordinary qualities, but that is a secondary 
consideration. What makes the garment a mag^c cloak is 
the fact that it has such properties, no matter where or how 
it got them. Or what is a magic change ? Is it merely a 
change wrought by spirits good or evil? By no means. 
27] 7^ 



28 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [28 

It IS any change with characteristics and results which we 
do not expect nor usually see in changes. In short, magic 
is pra&tematural rather than supernatural. 

Thus we find the existence of magic in the earliest period 
of human thought generally assumed by anthropologists, 
but some writers deny that man always has believed in 
supernatural beings. He first, they tell us, had a vague 
notion that by propitiating or by coercing nature he might 
secure for himself happiness ; and that if anything external 
was to have power over the workings of the natural struc- 
ture, it must be man, for both gods and God were yet un- 
known. Only gradually, they hold, through his belief in 
tree-spirits, through his devotion to plants or fetishes made 
sacred by their supposed efficacy in serving human wishes, 
perhaps, too, through his attitude toward human beings 
whose reputation for skill in magic finally led to deification, 
did man come to a belief in more or less divine beings and 
turn to them for the power and the happiness which in his 
savage and untutored impotency he had been unable to vv^in 
by his own efforts.^ Then only would the performance of 
magic by the aid of supernatural beings commence. 

There is another misleading idea which we should avoid. 
Fairy tales and romances picture magicians to us as few 
in number, adepts in a secret art. Instinctively, moreover, 
looking as we do upon magic as a mere delusion, we are 
prone to regard it as the creation of the popular imagina- 
tion, and to believe that what magicians there were outside 
of the ordinary man's imagination were a few imposters 
who took advantage of his fancies, or a few self-deceived 

1 This view is set forth at length in J. G. Frazer's The Golden Bough 
(3 vols., London, 1900). The book also furnishes many illustrations 
of the magic of primitive man. Mr. Frazer holds that " religion " sup- 
planted magic and is in turn itself being supplanted by science. His 
definition of religion would probably not be generally accepted. 



29] ORIGINS AND RELATIONS TO SCIENCE 29 

dreamers whose minds such fancies had led astray. This 
is a superficial view. It does not explain how the ordinary 
man came to imagine the existence of magic. Magicians 
in the true sense were no mere imaginary order existent only 
in the minds of men, nor a profession of dreamers and im- 
posters. Magic was not the outright invention of imaginzi^r ' / 
tion ; it was primitive man's philosophy, it was his attitude to^j 
ward nature. It was originally not the exercise of supposed ' 
innate, marvelous powers by a favored few nor a group of \ 
secret doctrines or practices known to but a few ; it was a j 
body of ideas held by men universally and which, during \ 
their savage state at least, they were forever trying to put \ 
into practice. Everybody was a magician. 

To understand magic, then, we should consider this atti- 
tude of primitive man — ^I use the word primitive in no nar- 
row sense — and should try to picture to ourselves what his 
attitude would be. It is a safe assumption that he would 
interpret the world about him according to his own sensa- 
tions, feeling? and motives. Whether he looked upon na- 
ture at large or in detail, he would in all probability regard 
it not as an inexorable machine run in accordance with 
universal and immutable laws, but as a being or world of 
beings much like himself — fickle, changing, capable of be- 
ing influenced by inducements or deterred by threats, benefi- 
cent or hostile according as satisfied or offended by treat- 
ment received. To make life go as he wished, he must 
be able to please and propitiate or to coerce these forces 
outside himself.^ In this endeavor his faculty of associa- 

^ Alfred Maury, in the introduction to his La Magie et I'astrologie 
dans Vantiquiti et au moyen age, (Paris, i860), expresses a practically 
identical view and has the conception of magic gradually fading away 
before the advance of science. (See also the article on " Magic" in the 
Encyclopedia Brittanica, 9th edition.) 

Maury's work is not, however, as satisfactory as one is led to think 



30 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [30 

tion probably led him to conclude that things resembling 
each other or having any seeming connection must be re- 
lated by strong bonds of sympathy and have power over 
each other. Since he had already attributed human char- 
acteristics to matter, he naturally now observed no distinc- 
tion between the animate and the inanimate, the material 
and the spiritual. A wooden image might be used to affect 
the fate of a human being, or the utterance of alluring and 
terrifying sounds to produce change in unfeeling and un- 
responsive matter. 

Moreover, as man observed the world about him, he 
would note many a phenomenon in nature which he could 
explain only by assuming strange and subtle influences. 
There was, for instance, the magnet, so different from 
other stones ; the hot spring, so different from other waters ; 
the action of electricity — still a mystery. Such things, too, 
as a calf with five legs, a dream, a sneeze, appealed to him 
as peculiar and striking, and perplexed him. He thought 
that they must have some important significance. His 
attempt to explain all such phenomena generally led him 
into magic. 

from reading its introduction. Although he has defined magic almost 
in so many words as the attitude of primitive man towards the universe, 
he himself interprets magic much more narrowly when he comes to 
write his book proper, as indeed its title, Magic and Astrology, suggests. 
In short the thought that science and magic may at one time have 
mingled does not seem to impress him, and his work is of little aid to 
one considering our present subject. For instance, he cites Pliny only 
as an opponent of magic Maury's work, moreover, comprising in its 
historical portion but a little over two hundred pages — and these nearly 
half filled by foot-notes— can hardly be regarded as more than a brief 
narrative sketch of the subject. 

Considerable erudition is displayed in Maury's references, especially 
those to Greek and Roman writers, and from page 208 to 211 Maury 
gives a good bibliography of some of the chief secondary works dealing 
with magic. More was written upon the subject shortly ibefore his time 
than has been since. 



31 ] ORIGINS AND RELATIONS TO SCIENCE 31 

Man often had to decide between two or more courses of 
action, apparently equally pleasing and advantageous or 
displeasing and disadvantageous. Should he turn to the 
right or to the left; should he begin his journey to-day or 
to-morrow? The thought probably came to him that one 
of these directions, one of these days, would in the end 
prove more advantageous than the other, though at present 
he could see no difference between them. One must be 
lucky, the other unlucky. This belief in lucky times, places 
and actions was magic. For such times, places and actions 
were magical as truly as the cloak that is unlike other cloaks 
or the change that differs from other changes. 

Akin to man's desire to discover what course of action 
would bring him' good luck was the longing he doubtless 
had to know the future; a knowledge which would be as 
interesting as those tales of his ancestor's doings in which 
he delighted, and of more practical use. As he had no diffi- 
culty in granting to matter spiritual qualities or in subject- 
ing to. trivial material influences mind and soul without 
power of resistance, so now he sought in the present sure 
signs of his own future. Such indications seemed to him to 
be found not only in dreams, which indeed had some con- 
nection with his personality, but also in such things as the 
flight of birds or the movements of the stars. He often did 
more than assign magic powers to the heavenly bodies; 
often he worshiped them as gods. His effort thus to learn 
the future from inadequate and irrelevant present phenom- 
ena was divination or magic. 

These notions of primitive man do not exhaust the field 
of magic. As he became educated, he would extend the 
attribution of magic properties to such things as numbers 
and written characters or formulae. His original ideas 
might be elaborated or refined. • But already he accepted the 
principles upon which a belief in magic founds itself. These 



32 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [32 

principles were evidently common property. Of course 
some men would come to surpass others in their knowledge 
of the supposed bonds of sympathy between diflFerent things, 
or of ludcy objects, seasons and methods, of ways to coax 
and control natural forces, of the meaning of portents and 
of means to predict the future In the progress of time the 
finer mysteries of the art might become the monopoly of a 
priesthood. But everybody believed in magic; everybody 
understood something about it. 

To attempt to define magic further than has been done 
in our description of the notions of primitive man is like 
trying to embrace a phantom. Mag^c rested upon man's 
conjecture of the characteristics and processes of nature, 
not on a knowledge of nature correctly deduced from ob- 
servation and experiment. As one would expect, there 
went with these mistaken notions a fantasticalness both in 
reasoning and in practical procedure. The follower of 
magic is apt to be on the watch not for facts or laws, but 
for hidden mysteries ; he is fond of ceremonial and symbols ; 
he enjoins upon himself and his fellows the necessity of 
secrecy in their operations and mysticism in their writings. 
Again, magic is, as has been said, praetematural ; its out- 
come is to be marvelous. It assumes the existence of won- 
derful properties in various objects and of wonderful bonds 
of S3anpathy between different things. Finally, we should 
remember that man always is a factor in magic. His knowl- 
edge, skill or power is always essential to the performance 
of a feat of magic. Even when demons do the deed, they 
must be invoked. A miracle may be contrary to natural 
law but it is not magic, for man is not the cause of it. 
Even if wrought in answer to his prayer, the miracle is not 
magic, for the gods answer only if they dioose But the 
magic formula compels the desired marvel; by it man co- 
erces nature or even deity. 



33] ORIGINS AND RELATIONS TO SCIENCE 33 

Such are some of the chief characteristics of magic. Yet 
with these granted, it remains, like superstition or religion, 
a vague term at best. The reader may disagree with me 
as to exactly what beliefs and practices should be included 
under it, and it is indeed a nice question just where magic 
begins and ends. Much of alchemy, for example, was noth- 
ing but chemistry of a rude sort, and perhaps even its the- 
ories that metals may be transmuted and life greatly pro- 
longed will some day prove to have had much truth in 
them. On the other hand, alchemy was based to a consid- 
erable extent on a belief that plants, animals and minerals 
have properties and powers which they cannot have: and if 
we ever do succeed in making gold or putting off old age, 
it is quite certain that such a consummation will never be 
accomplished by the fantastic methods which alchemists 
usually employed. Similarly we shall see that the practice 
of allegorical interpretation of past writings and the Pyth- 
agorean doctrine of numbers, which perhaps at first thought 
one would not regard as magic at all, nevertheless bear at 
least some resemblance to it. But after all our thesis is not 
to establish a certain definition for the word " magic," or 
to prove that such and such ideas and acts are magical. 
A name signifies little, and the word magic has had too 
many different meanings in different periods and for differ- 
ent men to allow any one to assert with confidence that he 
has found an absolutely correct definition. I employ the 
word simply because it seems the most convenient, most in- 
telligible and most justifiable tenri tor denoting a number 
of beliefs which I believe are all intimately related and 
which are the marks of a certain attitude towards the world. 

So much for the definition of magic and for the nature 
of its origin. But the discussion of these two points does 
not fully explain the meaning of the beliefs which were 
illustrated in our first chapter. We have yet to bring out 






34 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [34 

the full significance of the presence of such notions in the 
minds of mediaeval thinkers and scientists. 

It was stated above that the outcome of mag^c is praeter- 
natural, marvelous; but this statement, while in one sense 
perfectly true, requires some qualification. Perhaps to in- 
experienced primitive man the results which he wished to 
accomplish or the crude theories on which he based his 
operations seemed nothing remarkable. Perhaps incanta- 
tion seemed to him the natural way to bring rain, and sor- 
cery the sole cause of disease. But as time went on and 
observation taught men, it must have been impressed upon 
their minds that either the events they sought to produce, or 
the methods by which they sought to produce them, were a 
little out of the ordinary, although of the possibility of the 
events and of the validity of the methods they still remained 
\ convinced. If we wish to sum up the whole history of 
magic in a sentence, we may say that men first regarded 
magic as natural, then as marvelous, then as impossible and 
{ absurd. Evidently then magic is subjective, as anything- 
I false must be. To-day in the thought of educated and sen- 
sible people it is limited in actual significance to stage illu- 
sions ; once it was a universal attitude towards the universe. 
As one' false hypothesis after another was superseded by- 
true notions, the content of magic narrowed in men's 
minds until at last it became an acknowledged deception. 
Meanwhile its mistaken premises and strange proceedings 
first mingled with and then vanished into science and scien- 
tific methods. 

This, then, is the significance of the beliefs of which we 
were speaking in the first chapter. They are phenomena in 
that union — or struggle — of magic and science which 
marked the decay of the former and the development of the 
latter. As such, they warn us not to picture a magician to 
ourselves as armed with a wand, clad in solemn robes, 



35] ORIGINS AND RELATIONS TO SCIENCE 35 

and attended by a black cat. They warn us, on the other 
hand, not to regard the learned students of nature, mathe- 
matics and medicine in ages past as modem scientists in 
mind and spirit, who were merely handicapped by such ob- 
stacles as crude instruments and want of data. We per- 
ceive the anachronism involved in explaining away as mere 
passing fancies, personal eccentricities or anomalous beliefs 
the superstitious or bizarre notions of those to whom' tra- 
dition has accorded great fame. We are warned to con- 
sider carefully whether such notions were not ingrained in 
the very being of those men and characteristic of their whole 
mental attitude. 

Science and magic are very unlike, but even the dis- 
tinction between East and West varies according to where 
the speaker takes his stand. We have come to regard 
science as abstract truth, scientific investigation as neces- 
sarily correct and sensible; we forget that science has a 
past. In their actual history science and magic were not 
unassociated. Scientists might accept magical doctrines 
and magic might endeavor to classify its fancies and to 
account for them by natural causes. Roger Bacon could 
regard the attainment of magical results as the great end of 
experimental science. Francis Bacon could place magic in 
the same category with metaphysics and physics. 

It is with this mingling of magic and science — or more 
broadly of magic with learning in general — in the history 
of our Western world that this essay has to do. It is a 
theme of no narrow interest. Such ideas as have been 
cited, not only held by the most learned men of the times 
but incorporated in their scientific and philosophical systems 
— in so far as they had any — deserve consideration in the 
history of science and philosophy as well as in that of 
magic, or in an investigation of the mental make-up of 
the men of the past. 



36 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [36 

While, however, the place of magic in the intellectual 
history of Europe is our general subject, the present essay- 
is far from being an attempt at a complete treatment of 
it. The aim is rather to illustrate that theme by a survey 
of learning during the period of the Roman Empire, when 
the divers threads of the thought and knowledge of the 
ancient world were to some extent united. The prominence 
of magic in mediaeval science is perhaps better known and 
more generally admitted. Accordingly this essay will take 
for granted, except in so far as it has been illustrated in 
our first chapter, the presence of magic in mediaeval learn- 
ing, and will try to show that magical doctrines, credulity, 
mysticism, and love of the marvelous were not traits pecu- 
liar to mediaeval thought, but that in this respect (as in 
others) there was close resemblance, probably strict con- 
tinuity between the Roman world and later times. It was 
largely in order to bring out this resemblance, continuity 
and influence that the beliefs of various writers in the 
Middle Ages and early modern times were given in the 
first chapter. Let the reader compare them with those 
notions of men in the Roman Empire which will pres- 
ently be set forth. If we are justified in thus regarding- 
the Roman world as summarizing ancient science and 
helping to explain mediaeval thought, we evidently, in tak- 
ing our stand in that period secure a broad prospect and 
ought to obtain a fair idea of the place of magic in the 
intellectual history of Europe. In defining the field which 
we are to cover, it should be further said that Chris- 
tian thought will not come into our discussion, since it did 
not greatly influence science and other secular learning until 
the close of the Roman Empire. Lastly, it should be clearly 
understood that we are here concerned with magic only as 
connected with science and with learning — only as accepted 
by educated men. 



CHAPTER III 

Pliny's Natural History 

We should have to search long before finding a better 
starting-point for the consideration of the union of magic 
with the science of the Roman Empire and of the way in 
which that union influenced the Middle Ages than Pliny's 
Natural History. Its encyclopedic character affords a 
bird's-eye view of our entire subject. Its varied contents 
suggest practically all the themes of our discussion in suc- 
ceeding chapters. Chronologically considered, it is satis- 
factory as an introduction, since it appeared in the early 
part of the Empire (77 a. d.). 

I. The character of the work. — Pliny's treatise is far 
more than what we understand by a " Natural History." 
It is an attempt to cover the whole field of science; rerum 
natura is its subject.^ This, as Pliny says, is a task which 
no single Greek or Roman has before attempted. He tells 
us that he treats of some 20,000 topics gleaned from the 
perusal of about 2,000 volumes, with the addition of many 
facts not contained in previous works and only recently 

^ " Praeterea iter est, non trita auctoribus via, nee qua peregrinari 
animus expetat. Nemo apud nos qui idem temptaverit, nemo apud 
Graecos qui unus omnia ea tractaverit." From liis dedication to the 
Emperor Vespasian. C. Plinii Secundi, Naturalis Historiae Libri xxxvii. 
Ludovicus Janus, Lipsiae, 1870. 5 vols, in 3. I shall refer to passages 
by the division into chapters found in the editions of Hardouin, Valpy, 
Lemaire and Ajasson. Three modes of division are indicated in the 
edition of Janus. There is an English translation of the Natural His- 
tory, with an introductory essay, by J. Bostock and H. T. Riley, Lon- 
don, 1855, 6 vols. (Bohn Library). 

37] 37 



38 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [38 

brought to light/ At first thought, then, the Natural His- 
tory, vast in its scope and constituting a summary of the 
views of previous authorities, would seem the best sing-le 
example of the science of the classical world. The fact 
that it touches upon many of the varieties and illustrates 
most of the characteristics of magic makes it the more fit- 
ting a starting-point for us. Indeed, Pliny makes frequent 
mention of the Magi, and in the opening chapters of his 
thirtieth book gives the most important extant discussion of 
magic by an ancient writer. 

It is true, however, that Pliny does not seem to have 
been a man of much scientific training and experience. He 
said himself that his days were taken up with the perform- 
ance of public duties, and that consequently his scientific 
labors were largely carried on in the evening hours. ^ Prob- 
ably we should regard his book as little more than a com- 
pilation, and perhaps no very judicious compilation at that, 
in view of his maxim that there is no book so bad but that 
some good may be got from it.® Perhaps we may not un- 
justly picture him to ourselves as collecting his material in 
a rather haphazard fashion; as not always aware of the 
latest theories or discoveries; as occasionally citing a fan- 
tastic writer instead of a more sober one; or as quoting- 
incorrectly statements which his limited scientific knowledge 

1 " Viginti milia rerum dignarum cura ... ex lectione voluminum 
circiter duum milium, quorum pauca admodum studiosi attingunt 
propter secretum materiae, ex exquisitis auctoribus centum inclusimus 
xxxvi voluminibus, adiectis rebus plurimis quas aut ignoraverant priores 
aut postea invenerat vita." Also from the dedication. Pliny uses more 
than one hundred writers, however. 

2 " Homines enim sumus et occupati officiis, subcisivisque temporibus 
ista curamus, id est nocturnis, ne quis vestris putet cessatum horis." 
From the dedication. 

* Pliny the Younger to Macer in his Letters^ bk. iii, ep. 5, ed. Keil, 
Leipzig, 1896. 



\ Am^Jj-n *■' 



39] FLINT S NATURAL HISTORY 39 

prevented him from comprehending. Perhaps, too, he de- 
rived some of his data directly from popular report and 
superstition. Certainly to us to-day his work seems a dis- 
orderly and indiscriminate conglomeration of fact and 
legend on all sorts of subjects — disorderly, in that its 
author does not seem to have made any effort to sift his 
material, to compare and arrange his facts, even in his own 
mind ; indiscriminate, in that Pliny seems to lack any stand- 
ard of judgment, between the true and the false, and to 
deem almost nothing too improbable, silly or indelicate to 
be mentioned. Ought we to consider such a work as truly 
representative of the beliefs of preceding centuries, or as 
an example of the best educated thought and science of 
its author's own age? This is a question which we must 
consider. 

Yet as we read Pliny's pages we feel that he possessed 
elements of greatness. If he was equipped with little scien- 
tific training or experience, we should remember that little 
training or experience was necessary to deal with the science 
of those days. At least he sacrificed his life in an effort to 
investigate natural phenomena. Moreover, his faults were 
probably to a great extent common to his age. The ten- 
dency to regard anything written as of at least some value 
did not begin with him. Material had often before been 
collected in a haphazard manner. Lewes, in his book on 
the science of Aristotle, has described with truth even the 
famous History of Animals as unclassified in arrangement 
and careless in the selection of material.^ Many of Pliny's 
marvelous assertions and absurd remedies purport to be from 

1 Geo. H. Lewes, Aristotle; a Chapter from the History of Science^ 
London, 1864. Lewes also holds that while Aristotle often dwelt upon 

I 

the value of experiment and the necessity of having a mass of facts 
before making general assertions, he in practice frequently jumped at 
conclusions. 



40 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [40 

the works of men of note, although possibly he was some- 
times deceived by spurious writings. He frequently g^ves us 
to understand that he himself intends to maintain a cautious 
and critical frame of mind, and he makes great pretensions 
to immunity from that credulousness of human nature over 
which he will occasionally smile or philosophize.^ When 
we take up Aristotle's History of Animals and Seneca's 
Natural Questions, it will become evident that Pliny^s 
" science " was not very different in quality from that of 
the Greeks or from that of his own age. If he seldom 
gives us a clear-cut or complete exposition of a subject, it 
is probably because there was seldom one to be found. If 
he seems in a chronic statp of mental confusion and inco- 
herency, it is because his task staggered him. His work was 
by its nature so far impersonal that we can attribute its 
defects only in part to his personality. 

On the whole, then, we probably shall not be greatly mis- 
led if we regard the Historia Naturalis as a sort of epitome 
of what men had believed about nature in the past or did 
believe in Pliny's own day. The author may not have por- 
trayed past and present thought at their best but he por- 
trayed them, and that in detail. " The greatest gull of an- 
tiquity " ^ was the Boswell of ancient science. 

^ Nat, Hist, bk. xxvi, di. 9. "Mirum esset profecto hucusquc pro- 
feotam credulitatem antiquorum saluberrimis ortam initiis, si in ulla 
re modum humana ingenia novissent atque non banc ipsam medicinam ab 
Asclepiade repertam probaturi suo loco assemus evectam ultra Magos 
etiam. Haec est omni in re animorum condicio, ut a necessariis orsa 
primo cuncta pervenerint ad nimium." Cf. also bk. xxviii, ch. i. 
" Quamquam et ipsi consensu prope iudicata eligere laboravimus potius- 
que curae rerum quam copiae institimus." In Pliny's dedication, bow- 
ever, occurs a sentence which gives one the impression that be felt 
rather in duty bound to accept tradition. "Res ardua, vetustis novi- 
tatem dare, novis auctoritatem, obseletis nitorem, obscuris lucem, fas- 
tiditis gratiam, dubiis Mem, omnibus vero naturam et naturae suae 



omnia." 



2 Quoted without reference by E. Eggleston, The Transit of Civiliza- 



41 ] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 41 

Pliny makes almost as good a representative of mediaeval 
science as of that of the Roman world, and thus well illus- 
trates the influence which the one had upon the other. In- 
deed not only is the Natural History just the sort of work 
that delighted the Middle Ages, but Pliny seems to have 
exerted a considerable direct influence on writers down 
through the sixteenth century. Isidore of Seville practi- 
cally copied his unfavorable comments on the magi and his 
discussion of the powers of stones.^ Bede seems to have 
owed a good deal to him. Alcuin openly praised that 
" most devoted investigator of nature." ^ Roger Bacon 
quoted him; the Natural History was a mine whence 
Agrippa dug much of the material for his Occult Philosophy 
and to which Porta seems equally indebted in his Natural 
Magic. 

II. Pliny s discussion of magic. — Before illustrating 
Pliny's combination of magical lore with true and sane 
statements about nature, we should consider his discussion 
of what he was pleased to call magic; for just as he prided 
himself upon his freedom from excessive credulity in the 
abstract, so in regard to magic in particular he seems to 
have flattered himself that his position was quite different 
from- what it actually was. 

Hon from England to America in the Seventeenth Century** (N. Y., 
1901), p. 16. This interesting and valuable book contains much ma- 
terisft illustrative of the science and superstitions of the times. 

1 Etymologies, bk. xvi, Migne, vol. Ixxxii. 

2 Alcuini Epistolae, 103, vol. vi, pp. 431-432, of Bibliotheca Rerum 
Germanicarum, ed. Philip Jaff6, Berlin, 1873. "Vel quid acutius quam 
quod naturalium rerum divitissimus [or devotissimus] inventor, Plinius 
Secundus, de caelestium siderum ratione exposuit, investigari valet ?" In 
Migne's Patrologia Latina, vol. c, col. 278, the letter is given as num- 
ber 85. For other references to Pliny by earlier writers, see Bibliothique 
Latine-Frangaise, C. L. F. Panckoucke, vol. cvi which forms the open- 
ing volume of Pliny's work in that set 



42 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [42 

Pliny did have, however, a fairly clear idea of the exten- 
sive scope of magic as well as of its great age and currency. 
Not only did he declare that of all known arts it had exerted 
the greatest influence in every land and in almost every ag'e, 
but " no one," he said, " should wonder that its authority 
has been very great, since it alone has embraced and com- 
bined into one the three other subjects which appeal most 
powerfully to man's mind." ^ For magic had invaded the 
domain of religion and had also made astrology a part of 
itself,^ while " no one doubts that it originally ^rang from 
medicine and crept in under the show of promoting health 
as a loftier and more holy medicine." * Indeed, he thinks 
that the development of magic and of medicine have been 
parallel * and that the latter is now in imminent danger of 
being overwhelmed by the follies of magic which have made 
men doubt whether plants possess any medicinal properties 
at all.*' Pliny, moreover, sees the connection of magic with 
the lore of the magi of Persia. Indeed, " magus " is his 
only word for a magician. But this does not lead him to 
admit what some persons — ^the philosopher Eudoxus, for 
instance — ^have asserted, that magic is the most splendid 
and useful branch of philosophy.® For Pliny, magic is 
always something reprehensible. 

The magi are either fools or imposters. They are a 

1 Nat. Hist.y bk. xxx, ch. i. "Auctoritatem ei maxumam fuisse nemo 
miretur, quandoquidem sola artium tris alias imperiosissimas humanae 
mentis conplexa in unam se redigit." 

2 Ihid. He uses the words " mathematicas artes " ins-tead of '* as- 
trologiam " but the words following make his meaning evident : " nuUo 
non avido f utura de sese sciendi atque ea e caelo verissime pati credente." 

8 Ihid. " Natam primum e medicina nemo dubitat ac specie salutari 
inrepisse velut altiorem sanctioremque medicinam." 

* Bk. xxx, ch. 2. ^ Bk. xxvi, ch. 9. 

8 Bk. xxx, ch. 2. " Eudoxus qui inter sapientiae sectas clarissimam 
utilissimamque eam intellegi voluit." 



43] FLINT S NATURAL HISTORY 43 

genus vanissimum,^ They believe such absurdities as that 
herbs can dry up swamps and rivers, open all barriers, 
turn hostile battle-lines in flight, and insure their possessor, 
wherever he may be, abundant provision for every need.^ 
They make statements which Pliny thinks must have been 
dictated by a feeling of contempt and derision for the 
human race. They affirm that gems carved with the names 
of sun and moon and attached to the neck by hairs of the 
cynocephalus and feathers of the swallow will neutralize the 
effect of potions, win audience with kings, and, with the 
aid of some additional ceremony, ward off hail and locusts.* 
They have the impudence to assert that the stone " helio- 
tropium," combined with the plant of the same name and 
with due incantations, renders its bearer invisible.* " Van- 
itas " is Pliny's stock-word for their statements. Nero 
proved how hollow are their pretenses by the fact that, al- 
though he was most eagerly devoted to the pursuit of magic 
arts and had every opportunity to acquire skill in them, he 
was unable to effect any marvels through their agency and 
abandoned the study of them.*' 

1 Bk. xxviii, ch. 23. 2 gk. xxvi, ch. 9. 

8 Bk. xxxvii, ch. 40. The word in this passage which I render as 
"potion" is in the Latin "veneficium" — a word difficult to translate 
owing to its double meaning. "Venenum" signifies a drug or potion 
of any sort, and then in a bad sense a drug used to poison or a potion 
used (to bewitch. In a passage soon to be cited Pliny contrasts " vene- 
fica artes '* to " magicae artes " but I doubt if he always preserved such 
a distinction. A similar confusion exists in regard to the Greek word 
0(ip/za/cov, as Plato sets forth clearly in his Laws, There are, he says, 
two kinds of poisons employed by men which cannot be clearly dis- 
tinguished. One variety injures bodies "accordmg to a natural law." 
"There is also another kind which persuades the more daring class 
that they can do injury by sorceries and incantations . . ." Laws, 
bk. xi, p. 933 (Steph.). Jowett's translation. 

* Bk. xxxvii, ch. 60. " Magorum inpudentise vel manifestissimum in 
hac quoque exemplum est . . ." 

^ Bk. XXX, ch. 5, 6. 



44 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [44 

Moreover, magi or magicians deal with the inhuman, the 
obscene and the abominable. Osthanes, and even the phil- 
osopher Democritus, are led by their devotion to magic into 
propounding such remedies as drinking human blood or 
utilizing in magic compounds or ceremonies portions of the 
corpses of men violently slain. ^ Magic is a malicious and 
criminal art. Its devotees attempt the transfer of disease 
from one person to another or the exercise of baleful sor- 
cery.^ " It cannot be sufficiently estimated how great a 
debt is due the Romans who did away with those monstrous 
rites in which to slay a man was most pious ; nay more, to 
eat men most wholesome." ' In fine, we may rest per- 
suaded that magic is " execrable, ineffectual and inane." 
Yet it possesses some shadow of truth, but is of avail 
through " veneficas artes . . . non magicas/' * whatever 
that distinction may be. 

III. Illustrations of Pliny's fundamental belief in magic. 
— Pliny, we have seen, made a bold pretense of utter disbelief 
in magic, and also censured the art on grounds of decency, 
morality and humanity. Yet despite this wholesale con- 
demnation, in some places in his work it is difficult to tell 
where his quotations from magicians cease and where state- 
ments which he accepts recommence. Sometimes he ex- 
plicitly quoted theories or facts from the writings of the 
" magi " without censure and without any expression of 
disbelief. If it is contended that he none the less regarded 

1 Bk. xxviii, ch. 2. Pliny's own medicine is not prudish, and else- 
where he gives instances of devotees of magic guarding against defile- 
ment. (Bk. XXX, ch. 6 and xxviii, ch. 19). 

2 Bk. xxviii, ch. 23. " Quanta vanitate," adds Pliny, " si falsum est, 
quanta vero noxia, si transferunt morbos !" 

8 Bk. xxx, ch. 4. 

* Bk. xxx, ch. 6. " Proinde ita persuasum sit, intestabilem, inritam, 
inanem esse, habentem tamen quasdam veritatis umbras, sed in his 
veneficas artis pollere non magicas." 



45] FLINTS NATURAL HISTORY 45 

them as false and worthless, we may fairly ask, why then 
did he give them such a prominent place in his encyclo- 
pedia? Surely we must conclude either that he really had 
a liking for them himself and more than half believed them, 
or that previous works on nature were so full of such mate- 
rial and his own age so interested in such data that he could 
not but include much of this lore. Probably both alterna- 
tives are true. Finally, many things which Pliny states 
without any reference to the magi seem as false and absurd 
as the far-fetched assertions which he attributes to them 
and for which he shows so much scorn. Indeed, it hardly 
seems paradoxical to say that he hated the magi but liked 
their doctrines. 

What clearer example of magic could one ask than the 
conclusion that the odor of the burning horn of a stag has 
the power of dispelling serpents, because enmity exists be- 
tween stags and snakes, and the former track the latter to 
their holes and extract the snakes thence, despite all resist- 
ance, by the power of their breath ? Or that on this same 
account the sovereign remedy for snake-bite comes " ex 
coagulo hinnulei matris in utero occisi?" Or that, since 
the stag is not subject to fever, the eating of its flesh will 
prevent that disease, especially if the animal has died of a 
single wound ? What more magical than to fancy that the 
longest tooth of a fish could have any eflicacy in the cure 
of fever? Or that excluding the person who had tied it on 
from the sight of the patient for five days would complete 
a perfect charm ? Or that wearing as an amulet the carcass 
of a frog, minus the claws and wrapped in a piece of russet- 
colored cloth, would be of any aid against disease? ^ Yet 
the Natural History is full of such things. 

To plants, for example, Pliny assigns powers no less 

1 Concerning the stag, see bk. viii, ch. 50. On the use of frogs and 
fishes to cure fevers, bk. xxxii, ch. 38. 



46 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [46 

marvelous than those which he has attributed to atiinmls. 
There is one plant which, held in the hand, has a beneficial 
effect upon the groin; ^ another overcomes the asp with tor- 
por, and hence, beaten up with oil, is a remedy for the sting 
of that snake. ^ Fern, he says, if mowed down with the edge 
of a reed or uprooted by a ploughshare on which a reed has 
been placed, will not spring up again.' Moreover, in his 
twenty-fourth book, immediately after having announced 
that he has sufficiently discussed for the present the marvd- 
our properties attributed to herbs by the magi,* he proceeds 
to mention the following remedies. One is a quick cure 
for headache, and consists in gathering a plant growing on 
the head of a statue and attaching it to your neck with a 
red string. Another is a cure for tertian fever, and con- 
sists in plucking a certain herb before sunrise on the banks 
of a stream and in fastening it to the patient's left arm 
without his knowledge. A third recipe instructs us that 
plants which have taken root in a sieve that has been thrown 
into a hedge-row "decerptae adalligataeque gravidis partus 
adcelerant." A fourth would have herbs growing on dung- 
hills a cure for quinzy, and a fifth assures us that sprains 
may be speedily cured by the application of a plant " iuxta 
quam canes urinam fundunt," torn up by the roots and not 
allowed to touch iron.*^ 

Coming to minerals we find Pliny rather more reticent 
in regard to strange qualities. His account of gems is writ- 
ten mainly from the jeweler's point of view. When mar- 
velous powers are mentioned, the magi are usually made re- 

1 Bk. xxvi, ch. 59. 2 Bk. xxi, ch. 105. 

* Bk. xviii, ch. 8. * Bk. xxiv, ch. 102. 

^ Bk. xxiv, chs. 106, 107, 109, no, in. Evidently these last remedies 
derive their force not merely from magic powers inherent in vege)tatioa. 
The effect of ceremony and of circumstance becomes a factor. 



47] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 47 

Sponsible, and such powers are frequently rejected as ab- 
surd. Pliny, however, grants some magic properties in 
certain stones. Molochitis, by some medicinal power which 
it possesses, guards infants against dangers ; ^ and eumecas, 
placed beneath the head at night, causes oracular visions.^ 
To water Pliny allows powers which we must regard as 
magical, for according to him certain rivers pass under the 
sea because of their hatred of it.* 

In man, moreover, as well as in other creatures upon 
earth, there is magic power. Pliny mentions men whose 
eyes are able to exert strong fascination,* others who fill 
serpents with terror and can cure snake-bite by merely 
touching the wound, and others who by their presence addle 
eggs in the vicinity.*^ Pliny takes up the power of words 
and incantations in connection with man. Whether they 
have potency beyond what we expect ordinary speech to 
possess is a great and unanswered question. Our ancestors, 
Pliny says, always believed so, and in every-<iay life we 
often unconsciously accept such a view ourselves. If, for 
instance, we believe that the Vestal virgins can, by an im- 
precation, stop runaway slaves who are still within the city 
limits, we must accept the whole theory of the power of 
words. But, taken as individuals, the wisest men lack faith 
in the doctrine.® 

1 Bk. xxxvii, ch. 36. 2 gk. xxxvii, ch. 58. 

» Bk. ii, ch. 106. 

* Bk. vii, ch. 2. ". . . Qui visu quoque effascinent interimantque quos 
diutius intueantur, iratis praecipue oculis, quod eorum malum facilius 
sentire puberes. Notabilius esse quod pupillas binas in singulis habeant 
oculis." 

^ Bk. xxviii, ch. 6. The eggs, however, it should be said, are rep- 
resented as being beneath a setting hen. 

® Bk. xxviii, ch. 3. "Ex homine remediorum primum maxumae quaest- 
ionis et semper incertae est, polleatne aliquid verba et incantamenta 



A 










i» - ■ - - ^ 



■ ■J ■■ *• 



srmT :c r=r 



C ^ -111 mr 










s T 



•ic 



« < .. 







*5t'^tt4 -srv* rr.ds:-:y-A f-i^r::Ti rtcntr* ci ii-r:- j-r»c*rj 






w'^/T'l^ t// cii« <3:iesti6a vhethcr the go<li assvcr pizfcr or not, a 
tv>f* -Mrhi^h u^«% ui </at of the field of magic tailess be rrgarded 
M a rtt^AM of o>trcing the gods. 



49] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 49 

patient be fasting. Touching the sufferer with the back of 
her hand, she is to say, "Apollo forbids a disease to increase 
which a naked virgin restrains." Then, withdrawing her 
hand, she is to repeat the same words thrice and to join 
with the patient in spitting on the ground each time.^ 

Pliny occasionally prefaces his marvelous remedies by 
some such expression as " it is said." This circumstance 
is scarcely to be taken as a sign of mental reservation, how- 
ever, as the following absurd statement, which he makes 
upon his own authority and declares is easily tested by ex- 
periment, will indicate. " If a person repents of a blow 
given to another, either by hand or with a missile, let him 
spit at once into the palm of the hand which inflicted the 
blow, and all resentment in the person struck will instantly 
vanish." This is often proved, according to Pliny, in the 
case of beasts of burden, which can be induced to increase 
their speed by this method after the use of the whip has 
failed.^ 

One can, perhaps, make some distinction between the 
strange influences which Pliny credited and the statements 
of the magi which he rejected. I believe that he did not 
go to the length of affirming that plants or parts of animals 
could cause panics, procure provisions, win you royal favor, 
gain for you vengeance on your enemies, or make you in- 
visible. But he was inconsistent enough. After asserting 
that a single fish but a few inches long could immediately 

1 Bk. xxvi, ch. 60. " Expert! adfiTmavere plurumum ref erre, si virgo 
inx>onat nuda ieiuna ieiuno et manu supina tangens dioat; 'N^^at 
Apollo pestem posse crescere cui nuda virgo restinguat/ atque ita 
retrorsa inanu ter dicat totiensque despuant amibo." 

2 Bk. xxviii, ch. 7. " Mirum dicimus, sed experimento facile : si quern 
paeniteat ictus eminus comminusve inlati et statim exspuat in mediam 
manum qua percussit, levatur ilico in percusso culpa. Hoc saepe delum- 
bata quadripede adprobatur statim a tali remedio correcto animalis 
ingressu." 



50 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [50 

arrest the progress of the largest vessel by attaching itself 
to the keel of the ship/ was it for him to declare false the 
notion that a stone can calm winds or ward off hail and 
swarms of locusts ? He characterized as "idle talk" the as- 
sertion of the magi that the stone "gorgonia" counteracted 
fascination,* but he had already written : " Id quoque con- 
venit, quo nihil equidem libentius crediderim, tactis omnino 
menstruo postibus inritas fieri magorum artes, generis van- 
issimi, ut aestimare licet." ^ Apparently, then, the only 
charge which he could bring against magicians without re- 
flecting upon himself was that of malicious and criminal 
practices. His beliefs were much like theirs. 

Indeed, the varieties of magic in the Natural History 
have not yet been exhausted. For one thing, we must con- 
sider Pliny's position in regard to magic properties of the 
stars as well as of terrestrial matter. He believed in astrol- 
ogy, at least to some extent, although one might not think 
it if one read only the passage in which he speaks of the 
debt of gratitude mankind owe to the great geniuses who 
have freed them from superstitious fear of eclipses.* He 
could, nevertheless, in naming some prominent personage 
in each of the primary arts and sciences, mention Berosus, 
to whom a public statue has been erected by the Athenians 
in honor of his skill in prognostication, in connection with 
astrology.*^ 

Pliny himself holds that the universe is a divinity, " holy 
eternal, vast, all in all — nay, in truth is itself all," a propo- 

1 Bk. xxxii, di. i. * Bk. xxxvii, ch. 59. 

* Bk. xxviii, ch. 23. 

* Bk. ii, ch. 9. Indeed, in bk. ii, ch. 30, he gives examples of omin- 
ous elipses of the sun, although it is true that they were also of un- 
usual length. 

^ Bk. vii, ch. 37. " Astrologia Berosus cui ob divinas praedictiones 
Athenienses publice in gymnasio statuam inaurata lingua statuere." 



5 1 ] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 5 1 

sition rather favorable to astrological theory/ The sun is 
the mind and soul of the whole world and the chief gov- 
ernor of nature.^ The planets affect each other. A cold 
star renders another approaching it pale; a hot star causes 
its neighbor to redden; a windy planet gives those near it 
a lowering aspect.* Saturn is cold and rigid; Mars a flam-- 
ing fire; Jupiter, located between them, is temperate and 
salubrious.* When the planets reach a certain point in their 
orbits, they are deflected from their regular course by the 
rays of the sun.^ 

Besides effects upon each other the planets exert especial 
influence upon the earth. " Potentia autem ad terram mag- 
nopere eorum pertinens." ® They govern, each according 
to its nature, the weather on our globe."' The planets also 
have great influence upon diseases and on animal and plant 
life in general, although Pliny does not dwell upon this 
point at any length.^ The moon, a feminine and nocturnal 
star, stirs up humors on earth and is powerful in producing 

1 Bk. ii, ch. I. " Mundum . . . numen esse credi par est. Sacer est, 
aetemus, inmensus, totus in toto, immo vero ipse totum." 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 4. " Htmc esse mundi tatius animum ac planius mentem, 
hunc principale naturae regimen ac numen credere decet opera eius aes- 
timantes." 

* Bk. ii, ch. 16. * Bk. ii, ch. 6. ^ g^ ii, ch. 13. 

® Bk ii, ch. 6. See also bk. ii, ch. 39. " Ut solis ergo natura tem- 
perando intellegitur anno sic reliquorum quoque siderum propria est 
quibusque vis et a4 suam cuique naturam fertilis." 

"^ Bk. ii, ch. 39. For the general physical interaction of earth and 
stars as conceived by Pliny see bk. ii, ch. 38. " Terrena in caelum ten- 
dentia deprimit siderum vis, eademque quae sponte non subeant ad se 
trahit Decidunt imbres, nebulae subeunt, siccantur anmes, ruunt gran- 
dines, torrent radii et terram in medio mundi undique inpellunt, iidem 
infracti resiliunt et quae potuere auferunt secum. Vapor ex alto cadit 
rursumque in altum redit Venti ingruunt inanes iidemque cum rapina 
remeant Tot animalium hausitus spiritum e suiblimi trahit, at ille contra 
nititur, tellusquc ut inani caelo spiritum fundit." 

8 Bk. ii, ch. 41. 



52 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [52 

putrefaction and corruption in matter.* By the nature of 
Venus every thing on earth is generated.* 

To what extent the planets rule man's life Pliny does not 
specify — ^an instance of prudent reticence on his part, if he 
really consciously avoided the question. He disclaims any 
belief in the vulgar notion that a star, varying in brightness 
according to our wealth, is assigned to each of us, and that 
the eternal stars rise and fade at the birth or death of in- 
significant mortals. "Non tanta caelo societas nobiscum est 
ut nostro fato mortalis sit ibi quoque siderum fulgor." * 
But thus to deny that the stars are ruled by man's destiny 
or doings is far from refusing to believe that men's lives 
are ordered by the stars. Pliny, as we have seen, holds that 
Venus has a considerable influence over the process of birth 
in all animals. Also he certainly accepts the portentous 
character of various particular celestial phenomena. " From 
the stars celestial fire is vomited forth bearing omens of 
the futiu-e." * He gives instances from Roman history of 
comets which signalled disaster, expounds the theory that 
their significance is to be determined from the direction in 
which they move and the heavenly body whose powers they 
receive, and states that the particular phase of life to which 
they apply may be deduced from the shape which they 
assume or from their position in relation to the sig^ of the 
zodiac.** 

^ Bk. ii, ch. 104. 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 6. " Huius natura cimcta generantur in terris, namque 
in alterutro exortu genitali rore conspergens non terrae modo concep- 
tuus inplet verum animantium quoque omnium stimulat." 

* Bk. ii, ch. 6. 

* Bk. ii, ch. 18. " A sidere caelestis ignis exspuitur praescita secum 
adferens." 

^ Bk. ii, ch. 23. The part dealing with the shape and position of the 
comet reads : " Tibiarum specie musicae arti portendere, obscenis autem 
moribus in verendis partibus signorum, ingeniis et eruditioni, si tri- 



53] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 53 

Pliny's belief in portents seems to have been general and 
not limited to celestial phenomena. In a passage on earth- 
quakes he declares, " Never has the city of Rome shaken 
but that this was a forewarning of some future event." ^ 

Pliny is less certain in regard to the superstitious ob- 
servances so common then, to secure good luck or ward off 
evil fortune. In chapter five cJf his twenty-eighth book he 
gives quite a list of practices, such as selecting persons with 
lucky names to lead the victims at public lustrations, salut- 
ing those who sneeze, placing saliva behind the ear to escape 
mental anxiety, removing rings while eating, averting the 
ill-omen of mentioning fire at meal-time by pouring water 
beneath the table, and other superstitious table etiquette. He 
cites beliefs of the same nature, as that odd numbers are for 
every purpose the more efficacious, that medicines do no 
good if placed on a table before being administered, that 
baldness and headaches may be prevented by cutting the 
hair on the seventeenth and twenty-ninth days of the moon, 
and that women who walk along country roads twirling 
distaffs, or even having these uncovered, bring very bad 
luck, especially to the crops. He seems to have inclined to 
the belief that there was a modicum of truth, at any rate, 
in these notions and customs — ^and certainly we have already 
seen him affirming the validity of analogous practices — ^but 
he finally decides that amid the great variety of opinion ex- 
isting in the matter he will not be dogmatic and that each 
person may think as he deems best. His attitude is much 
the same in regard to divination from thunder and light- 
ning.^ 

quetram figuram quadratamve paribus angulis ad aliquos perennium 
stellarum situus edant, venena fundere in capita septentrionalis aus- 
trinaeve serpentis." 

1 Bk. ii, ch. 86. " Numquam urbs Roma tremuit, ut non futuri eventus 
alicuius id praenuntium esset/' See also bk. ii, ch. 85. 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 54. 



54 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [54 

With all the foolish notions which he imbibed from an- 
tiquity or into which his mind, over-hospitable to the fan- 
tastic and marvelous, led him, Pliny had one good scientific 
trait. He might believe in magic but he had no liking for 
the esoteric. His mind might be confused but it was not 
mystical. He had no desire to hide the " secrets " of 
science and philosophy from the public gaze, to wrap them 
up in obscure and allegorical verbiage lest the imworthy 
comprehend them. On the contrary, he sharply remarked 
apropos the lack of information about the medicinal prop- 
erties of plants, that there was a most shameful reason for 
this scarcity, namely, that even those who knew were un- 
willing to give forth their knowledge, " as if that would 
be lost to themselves which they passed on to others." ^ 

Such, then, is the Natural History. Pliny gives evidence 
that many of the most intelligent men were coming to 
doubt a large part of the superstitious beliefs and obser- 
vances once universally prevalent, and he himself makes a 
brave effort to assume a critical and judicious attitude. 
Yet his work contains a great deal of magic and reveals, 
what this essay in its entirety will make further evident, the 
error of such a statement as the following from Eh*. White's 
Warfare of Science and Theology: 

Under the old Empire a real science was coming in and 
thought progressing. Both the theory and practice of magic 
were more and more held up to ridicule. Even as early a 
writer as Ennius ridiculed the idea that magicians, who were 
generally poor and hungry themselves, could bestow wealth on 
others ; Pliny, in his Natural Philosophy, showed at great length 
their absurdities and cheatery ; others followed in the same line 

^ Bk. XXV, ch. 6. " Turpissima causa raritaitis quod etiam qui sciunt 
demon strare nolunt, tamquam ipsis periturum sit quod tradiderint aliis." 



..^.•aLii.M.Mt^^ ...I I. . 



55] PLINY'S NATURAL HISTORY 55 

of thought, and the whole theory, except among the very low- 
est classes, seemed dying out.^ 

1 Vol. i, p. 382. Dr. White's book, whidi imputes well-nigh every 
fantastic feature of mediaeval science to Christian institutions and theo- 
logy, is written with too little use of primary sources, and considerable 
ignorance of the character of ancient science. 

Aside from unfairness in the general tone and mode of presentation, 
— Cosmas Indicopleustes, for instance, is set forth as a typical representa- 
tive of mediaeval science of the clerical type, while Albertus Magnus 
is not permitted to stand as a representative of "theological" science 
at all but is pictured as one inclined to true science w'ho was frightened 
into the paths of theology by an ecclesiastical tyranny bitterly hostile 
to scientific endeavor — the author makes some inexcusable mistakes 
in details. For insitance, after speaking of "theological" methods, he 
proceeds (vol. i, p. 33) : "Hence such contributions as that the basilisk 
kills serpents by his breath and men by his glance," apparently in serene 
ignorance of the fact that this statement about the basilisk was a com- 
monplace of ancient science. Again (vol. i, p. 386) he tells us that in 
1 163 the Council of Tours and Alexander III "forbade the study of 
physics to ecclesiastics, which of course in that age meant the pro- 
hibition of all such scientific studies to the only persons likely to make 
them." On turning to the passage cited we find the prohibition to be 
that persons who have vowed to lead a monastic life shall not absent 
themselves from their monasteries for the purpose of studying "physica" 
(which the context indicates means medicine, not physics), or reading 
law. The canon does not apply to all ecclesiastics, and it is as absurd 
to infer from it that "all such scientific studies were prohibited to 
the only persons likely to make them" as to conclude that henceforth 
no one could study civil law. To argue from a single piece of legisla- 
tion is hazardous in any case. (For the canon, see Harduin, vol. vi, pt. 
ii, p. 1598. Canon viii.) 

On the whole the book strikes one as an unscientific eulogy of science 
and a bigoted attack on bigotry. The inconsistency of the author's 
professions and practice, to say nothing of the somewhat perplexing 
arrangement of his material, reminds one of Plinjr's Natural History, 



CHAPTER IV 

Some Antecedents of the Belief in Magic in the 

Roman Empire 

Writers who have discussed the intellectual life under 
the Roman Empire generally agree that it was not marked 
by originality and creative power, and owed a perhaps un- 
usually large debt to the past. The cosmopolitan character 
of the Empire, the mingling at that time of the science, 
theology, philosophy and superstition of different nations, 
religions and races, deserve equal emphasis. The lore of 
the magi of Persia, the occult science of Egypt, perhaps 
even the doctrines of the gymnosophists of India, may be 
regarded, together with that belief in divination which 
played such a role in classical religion and government and 
with other superstitious notions of Gredcs and Italians, as 
contributory to the prominence of mag^c in the Empire. 

To discuss with any attempt at completeness the influ- 
ence of the past upon the belief in magic in the Empire lies, 
however, outside the province of this essay. Pliny has 
shown us something of the union of magic with science in 
the literature before his day. Philo of Alexandria, Apu- 
leius and the fame of Hermes Trism^stus may give us 
some notion of the influence of the East. In other writers 
of the period of which we treat one may discern further 
traces of the thought and learning of the past. In general 
such evidence must suffice. We shall, however, presently 
take occasion to support our contention that Pliny gives one 
S6 [S6 



57] MAGIC BEFORE THE ROMAN EMPIRE 57 

a fairly good idea of science before his day, by a few cita- 
tions from two writers of repute, one a Greek and one a 
Roman, of the period before the Empire. Moreover, the 
great historical importance of Greek philosophy and the fact 
that, besides playing a prominent part in Roman culture, it 
exercised a powerful direct influence on Christian Europe 
long after the fall of Rome, seem to justify some treatment 
of its doctrines. Especially may we mention Plato and Aris- 
totle, who exerted great influence not only during classical 
times, but also the one in the Middle Ages, the other in the 
period following the decline of Scholasticism. 

We naturally incline to regard this earlier period of 
more or less distinctively Greek thought and learning as a 
golden age, comparatively speaking, characterized by sane 
thinking if not also by careful investigation of nature, and 
free from superstition, credulity and mysticism. The gen- 
eral opinion seems to be that magic entered science and 
learning and was accepted by men of intellectual promi- 
nence only when mental decay had set in and when Oriental 
influence had become a powerful force. 

Yet something might be said for the opposite view that 
this earlier age combined magic with its science and phil- 
osophy as much, if not more, than the later time. We know 
that Greek philosophy had its beginnings in mythology ; and 
if the representatives of its maturity accepted the Greek re- 
ligion with its auspices drawn from' sacrifices, its oracles 
and the like, we may with reason ask, is it probable that 
they would hesitate to give similar doctrines a place in their 
scientific and philosophical systems? Pliny, for his part, 
evidently regarded himself as less credulous and as less in- 
clined to magic than the ancient Greeks, although it is true 
that he attributed their belief to Oriental influence. He de- 
clared that Pythagoras, Empedocles, Democritus and Plato 
had learned the magic art abroad and had taught it on their 



58 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [58 

return.^ Beside the name of Hippocrates in the field of 
medicine he set that of Democritus in the domain of magic* 
Elsewhere he said that Pythagoras and Democritus, having 
embraced the doctrine of the magi, first expounded the 
properties of magic plants in the Western world.' In 
Cicero's De Divifiatione, Epicurus is alone of the Gredc 
philosophers declared free from trust in divination, and 
Panaetius is said to have been the only Stoic to reject 
astrology.* 

Fortunately we are not here concerned to measure either 
relatively or absolutely with any attempt at exactness the 
amount of magic in the learning of the closing centuries of 
Greek national life, but only to investigate whether in the 
philosophy of the Greeks there were not theories at least 
liable to encourage a later age to belief in magic. There 

^ Nat, Hist., bk. xxx, ch. 2. "Certe Pythagoras, Empedocles, De- 
mocritus, Plato ad banc discendam navigavere exsiliis verius quam pere- 
grinationibus susceptis. Hanc reversi praedicavere, banc in arcanis hab- 
uere." Philostratus, as we sball see, mentioned tbe same men as as- 
sociating witb the magi, although he denied that they embraced the 
magic art. (See infra, p. 66.) 

2 Bk. xxx, ch. 2. " Plenumque miraculi et hoc, pariter utrasque artis 
effloruisse, medicinam dico et magicenque, eadem aetate illam Hippocrate, 
hanc Democrito inlu&trantibus." Pliny may have got a false idea of the 
teachings of Democritus by accepting as genuine works which were 
not. He tells us (bk. xxx, ch. 2) that some persons have vainly tried 
to save Democritus' reputation by denying that certain works are ihis. 
" Democritus Apellobechen Coptiten et Dardanum et Phoenicem inlust- 
ravit voluminibus Dardani in sepulchrum eius petitis, suis vero ex dis- 
ciplina eorum editis, quae recepta ab ullis hominum atque transisse per 
memoriam aeque ac nihil in vita mirandum est In tantum fides istis 
fasque omne deest, adeo ut qui cetera in viro probant, haec opera eius 
esse inficientur. Sed frustra. Hunc enim maxume adfixisse animis earn 
dulcedinem constat." 

8 Bk. xxiv, ch. 9. " In promisso herbarum mirabilium occurrit aliqua 
dicere et de Magicis. Quae enim mirabiliores ? Primi eas in nostro 
orbe celebravere Pythagoras atque Democritus, consectati Magos." 

* De Divinatione, bk. i, ch. 39, and bk. ii, ch. 42. 



59] MAGIC BEFORE THE ROMAN EMPIRE 59 

was, for instance, the view of the Stoics that the universe 
is a single living whole — a theory well fitted to form the 
starting-point for a belief in sympathetic magic. Also their 
doctrine that events are all arranged in a fatal causal series 
was favorable to divination. Quintus Cicero, represented 
as upholding the truth of that art, cites the Stoics as author- 
ity, and we may safely assume that Seneca drew his view 
of divination largely from the same source. 

The doctrine of Pythagoras also deserves mention, for it 
has played a great role in history. He is said to have held 
that the whole world is, and that the life of man ought to 
be, harmoniously ordered in accordance with mathematical 
principles; nay more, that such principles are living things 
and that ntmibers are the essence of the universe. The log- 
ical conclusion is that by skilful use of mere numbers 
man can move heaven and earth. As the poet, eulogizing 
Michael Scot, put it ; the " mathematici " by their art affect 
numbers, by numbers affect the procession of the stars, and 
by the stars move the universe. The emplo)mient of char- 
acters constructed of numbers or of geometrical figures, the 
use of numerical formulae as remedies or of compounds of 
three portions of three kinds of drugs applied during three 
successive days, is raised from the plane of superstition to 
the level of science. It is not unreasonable to suppose that 
the heavenly bodies with their apparently unchanging regu- 
larity of movement are the governors of our existence. 
Plato, who adopted the Pythagorean doctrines at least to a 
considerable extent, declared that the loftiest function of the 
sense of sight was to survey the heavens, an occupation by 
which we gain philosophy.^ Like the Pythagoreans also, 

he associated the four elements with regular solids. The 

» 

1 Timaeus, p. 47 (St€ph.)- The passage may be found in English 
translation in vol. iii, p. 466, of B. Jowett's Plato's Dialogues (3d edit), 
London, 1892. 






6o MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [60 

cube represented earth; the cKtohedron was water; the tet- 
rahedron, fire; and the icosahedron, air.^ The remaining 
regular solid, the dodecahedron, was held to represent the 
universe as a whole. 

Towards magic, as he understood it, Plato's attitude 
seems to have been sceptical, though perhaps not confidently 
so. He maintained that persons acquainted with medicine 
and prophets or diviners were the only ones who could 
know the nature of poisons which worked naturally, and of 
such things as incantations, magic knots and waxen images ; 
and that since other men had no certain knowledge of such 
things, they ought not to fear but to despise them. He ad- 
mitted, however, that there was no use in trying to convince 
most men of this and that legislation against sorcery was 
necessary.^ He himself occasionally mentioned charms or 
soothsaying in a matter-of-fact way. 

Whatever Plato's opinion of vulgar magic, his view of 
nature was much like that of primitive man. He human- 
ized material objects and materialized spiritual character- 
istics. For instance, he asserted that the gods placed the 
lungs about the heart " as a soft spring that, when passion 
was rife within, the heart, beating against a yielding body, 
might be cooled and suffer less, and might thus become 
more ready to join with passion in the service of reason.'' * 
He affirmed that the liver was designed for divination, and 
was a sort of mirror on which the thoughts of the intellect 
fell and in which the images of the soul were reflected, but 
that its predictions ceased to be clear after death.* Plato 
spoke of the existence of harmonious love between the de- 

1 Timaeus, pp. 53-56 (Steph.) ; Jowett, vol. iii, pp. 473-476. 

^ Laws, bk. xi, p. 933 (Steph.). 

^ Timaeus, p. 70 (Steph.). The translation is that of Jowett, vol. iii, 
p. 492. 
*Ibid., p. 71 (Steph.). 



6i] MAGIC BEFORE THE ROMAN EMPIRE 6l 

ments as the source of health and plenty for vegetation, 
beasts and men. Their " wanton love " he made the cause 
of pestilence and disease. To understand both varieties of 
love " in relation to the revolutions of the heavenly bodies 
and the seasons of the year is," he tells us, " termed astron- 
omy." ^ This suggests that he believed in astrology — in 
the potent influence of the stars over all changes in earthly 
matter. He called the stars " divine and eternal animals, \) 
ever abiding." ^ The " lower gods," of whom many at 
least are identical with the heavenly bodies, form men who, 
if they live well, return after death each to a happy exist- 
ence in his proper star.® The implication is, though Plato 
does not say so distinctly, that the stars influence human life. 
Aristotle's doctrine was similar. Windelband has well 
expressed his view: 

The stars themselves were . . . for Aristotle beings of super- v / 
human intelligence, incorporate deities. They appeared to him /\ 
as the purer forms, those more like the deity, and from them a ^ 
purposive rational influence upon the lower life of the earth 
seemed to proceed — a thought which became the root of medi- 
aeval astrology.* 

Moreover, " his theory of the subordinate gods of the 
spheres of the planets . . . provided for a later demonol- . 
ogy." ^ And a belief in demons fosters a belief in magic. 
For such subordinate gods — on the one hand movers of 
nature's forces, and on the other hand subject to passions 
like man and open to influence through symbols and con- 

^ Symposium f p. i88 (Steph.). Translated by Jowett, vol. i, p. 558. 

2 TimaeuSy p. 40 (Steph.). Jowett, vol. iii, p. 459. 

^ Ibid., p(p. 41, 42 (Steph.). 

* W. Windelband, History of Philosophy, p. 147. English transla- 
tion by J. H. Tufts. Macmillans, 1898. 

« Windelband, Hist of Ancient Philos,, p. 272. Eng. transl. by H. E. 
Cushman. Scriibners, 1899. 



62 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [62 

jurations — are evidently most suitable agents for the worker 
of magic to employ. We must also mention Aristotle's 
attribution of " souls *' to plants and animals, a theory 
which would readily lend itself to an assumption of magic 
properties in herbs and beasts. 

Aristotle himself in his works upon natural science ac- 
cepts such properties to a considerable extent. A few cita- 
tions from his History of Animals ^ will show that we have 
not been misled in inferring from Pliny that Greek science 
at its best was not untainted by magic. The History of 
Animals seems to attribute undue influence to the full moon 
and the dog-star,^ and to hold that honey is distilled from 
the air by the stars and that the wax alone is made by the 
bees.^ Aristotle repeats the story that the salamander is a 
fire-extinguisher.* He mentions as a cure for the sting of 
a certain snake the drinking of a small stone " taken from 
the tomb of one of the ancient kings." Like Pliny, he 
makes human saliva a defense against serpents.*^ He sa)rs 
of certain things that they are ominous of certain events.* 

^ Aristotelis De Animalihus Historiae Libri X (Graece et Latine. 
lo. Gottlob Schneider. Lipsiae, 1811). Vol. i contains the Greek 
text In the following foot-notes I shall refer to the book, chapiter 
and section by Roman and arabic numerals, but in the text the book 
and chapters are denoted by letters of the Greek alphabet There is an 
English translation of the work by Richard Creswell, London, 1862. 
(Bohn Library.) 

2 Bk. V, ch. XX, sec. 2 ; bk. vi, ch. xi, sec. 2 ; bk. vi, ch. xiv, sec. i ; 
bk. vii, ch. xi; bk. viii, ch. xvii, sec. 4; bk. viii, ch. xx, sec 12. 

'Bk. V, ch. xix, sec. 4. ViyveTai 6k Kjjpiov fikv ef avOow. K^pcjaiv 6i 
(jfipaooLv airb tw duKpiov tqv SMpcjVj fikTu de to niKTOif e« tov dipog Koi jidTuara 
kv raZf rCnf aarpav kniToTialg, koi brav KardOK^ipy ij Ipig. 'OAwf 6' ov yiyverai fdJu 
irpib Tz'^iddog eTfiroTi^i. tov fiku ovv Krjpbv Trowel, oairep elprjTai, bk tCjv dvOicjVj rd 6i 
fiiXi bri ov TTOiel, d^XXd (pipei rb tt/tttov, aijfielov. kv fiig, yap ij kv dvalv ^jLiipaic 
irTJipTi evpioKovai rd a/i^ ol fie'XLTTOvpyol /liXiTog, 'En 6e tov /leroir^pov avOrj 
yiyverai fikvy fikh. 6* oi), brau d<l>aipedy, 

* Bk. V, ch. xvii, sec. 13. '^ Bk. viii, ch. xxviii, sec. 2. 

« Bk. iii, ch. ix, sec 7 and bk. vi, ch. ii, sec 4. 



63] MAGIC BEFORE THE ROMAN EMPIRE 63 

He affirms that the hen-partridge is affected by the mere 
breath of the cock or by a breeze from his direction/ He 
thinks that insects are spontaneously generated from mud, 
dung, wood, or flesh. ^ He says it is plain that the Narce 
causes stupefaction in both fish and men.® He has not only 
an idea that those with lice in their hair are less subject to 
headaches, but also a notion that those who have lice and 
take baths become more liable to the pest when they change 
the water in which they wash themselves.* Another amus- 
ing illusion which he records is that calves will suffer less 
in their feet if their horns are waxed.*^ Thus the pages of 
Aristotle give ground for belief that the fantasticalness of 
mediaeval science was due to " the clear light of Hellas " 
as well as to the gloom of the " Dark Ages." 

The book by a Roman which we are to consider as illus- 
trative of the condition of science before the age of the 
Empire is Cato's treatise on agriculture. Several passages 
emphasize the importance of such conditions as that the 
moon should be new or waning or not shining during the 
performance of such acts as the transplanting of trees or 
the manuring of meadows. • It is also directed that in ad- 
ministering medicine to oxen the man giving the dose shall 
have fasted previously and that both he and the ox stand 
upright during the operation.^ One medicine prescribed 

1 Bk. V, ch. iv, sec. 7 and bk. vi, ch. ii, sec. 9. See also bk. vi, ch. 
xvii, sec. 4. 

2 Bk. V, ch. xvii, sec. 2. » ^k, jx, ch. xxv, isec 2. 

* Bk. V, ch. xxv, sec. 2. '^ Bk. viii, ch. ix, sec. I. 

^ De Re Rustica, chs. 26, 31, 37, 40, 50. Scriptores Rei Rusticae 
Veteres Latini. Tomus Primus. lo. Matthias Gesnerus, Lipsiae, 1773. 
The speed wkh which I progn'essed through the De Re Rustica was 
accelerated by the fact that Mr. E. H. Oliver, Ph. D., then of the 
School of Political Science, Columbia University, kindly lent me an 
English translation which he had made of that work. 

'' De Re Rustica, ch. 71. See also ibid., ch. 70. 




64 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [64 

for cattle is a mixture of 3 grains of salt, 3 leaves of laurel, 
3 fibres of leek, 3 tufts of ulpicati ledc, 3 sprigs of the savin, 
3 leaves of rue, 3 stalks of the white vine, 3 white beails, 
3 live coals, 3 sextarii of wine. Each ox is to be given a 
portion for three days and the whole is to be divided so 
that it will suffice for exactly three doses. ^ To heal a sprain 
or fracture the singing of the following nonsensical incan- 
tation or formula is recommended : " In alios S. F. motas 
vaeta daries dardaries astataries dissunapiter." ^ This was 
written by a man generally supposed to have had much 
common sense and who was enlightened enough to wander 
how two augurs could let their eyes meet without laughing. 

^ De Re Rustica, ch. 70. 

2 De Re Rustica, ch. 160. " S. F." probably means " Sanitas Fraoto." 
Two alternative charms are also suggested, namely, " Huat hanat huat 
ista pista sista domiabo damnaustra " and " Huat huat huat ista sis tar 
sis ardannabon dunnaustra." 



CHAPTER V 

Belief in Magic in the Empire 

Having shown reason for believing that the Natural His- 
tory is a fairly accurate mirror of the science of the past, 
we come now to examine Pliny's own age and to observe 
to what extent his attitude towards magic was characteristic 
of it. " His own age," I say, but this is only roughly 
speaking, for it is the general period of the Roman Empire 
that we shall now consider, with the exception of the clos- 
ing century which we reserve for later discussion. We 
shall have now to speak first of the general attitude towards 
magic in the Empire, and then in particular of two or three 
men or works that corroborate the rich evidence which 
Pliny, for the most part unconsciously, gave of the place 
of magic in the intellectual life of the time. 

I. General attitude. — At the start, just as in our discus- 
sion of the Natural History, we find it necessary to distin- 
guish the position of men towards what they called "magic." 
Pliny's condemnation of the magi and of all their beliefs 
as a matter of general principle was probably the regular 
attitude. A stigma seems to have been attached to the word 
"magic ;" and magi seem to have been regarded as dangerous 
characters. In his history Dio Cassius represents Maecenas 
as warning Octavius Caesar that while the practice of divi- 
nation is necessary, and augury by sacrifices and flight of 
birds an art to be encouraged, magicians ought to be en- 
tirely done away with. For, telling the truth in some cases 
65] 6s 



66 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [66 

but lying in more, they incite many persons to revolt/ The 
prejudice in the Empire against magic is further illustrated 
by the fact that pagan and Christian controversialists seldom 
failed to impute to the opposing religion the practice of 
this malign art. 

Now and then some learned man like Eudoxus might 
hold that the doctrines of the magi of Persia called for 
eulogy rather than reproach. Thus Apuleius, in his Defense 
against the accusation of magic brought against him, ex- 
plained that magus in the Persian language was 
equivalent to the Latin sacerdos or priest, and that, 
among the four greatest men of the realm selected to edu- 
cate the heir to the Persian throne, one had the task of in- 
structing him in the magic of Zoroaster. This magic dealt 
with " the rules of ceremonial, the due observance of things 
sacred, the law of religious rites." ^ It was the cult of 
the gods. 

Do you hear, you who rashly charge me with magic, that this art 
is acceptable to the immortal gods, consists of celebrating and 
reverencing them, is pious and prophetic, and long since was 
held by Zoroaster and Oromagus, its authors, to be noble and 
divine ? Nay, it is included among the chief studies of royalty, 
and the Persians no more think of rashly allowing any one to 
become a magician than to become a king.* 

^Dio Cassius, ch. Hi, sec. 36. fiavriK^ fih yap avayKaia earl, ml ndvrt^ 
TLvag Kol kpdTTTag naX oluvLarag anddet^oVf dig oi Pov?i6/ievoi ri Koiv6aaa6ai aoviaovrai. 
Tovg 6e dr^ fiayevrdg Trdw ovk elvai irpoa^Kei. ttoXAovc yap 7ro22diuc ol roiovroi, rd 
fih TLva aTafi^, to. 6h 6^ TrAe/w ipevdy Xiyovreg, vevxf^ovv eiralpovai. 

Lecky translates the passage in his History of European Morals (1889), 
vol. i, p. 399. The next sentence of the passage is also worth qij 
rd d* avrb tovto koI t(jv ^i}\.oao<^Eiv TrpoaKoiovfiivoiv ovk bXiyoi noiovai, 

^Apologia, ch. xxv (Van der Vleet, Apologia et Floridi 
1900). "Leges cerimoniarum, fas sacrorum, ius religionum*' 

8 Ibid., ch. xxvi. "Auditisne, magiam, qui earn temere acci* 
esse diis immortalibus acceptam, colendi eos ac venerandi ; 





r 



67] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 67 

But if his accusers mean magic in the popular sense, that is, 
Apuleius grants, a different matter. 

Even educated men, however, probably more often, like 
Pliny, regarded the magi as all one with other magicians. 
Philostratus, in his life of ApoUonius of Tyana, seems to 
approximate much closer to this position than to that taken 
by Apuleius, although one would expect a biographer of 
that mystic personage to view the magi with favor. Philo- 
stratus declares that ApoUonius was no magician, although 
he did associate with the magi of Babylonia, the Brahmins 
of India, and the g3niinosophists of Egypt. For he was 
like Empedocles, Pythagoras, Democritus and Plato who fre- 
quented those sects and yet did not embrace the (magic) art.^ 

Of what we should call magic, however, there was a 
plenty in the Roman Empire, as in fact the words of Dio 
Cassius have indicated.^ Besides the general acceptance of 
divination there was a great deal of superstitious medicine. 
There seems to be little room for doubt that Pliny's dia- 
tribes against the medical art were justifiable, and that his 
own trust in marvelous medicinal properties of animals and 
plants was often equalled. Men of the highest eminence in 
public life, whom one would expect to have had at their 
disposal the best medical talent of the time, are reported to 

piam scilicet et divini scientem, aam inde a Zoroastro et Oromazo, auc- 
toribus suis nobilem, caelitum antistitam? Quippe qui inter prima re- 
galia docetur, nee ulli temere inter Persas concessum est magum esse, 
hand magis quam regnare/* This definition reminds one of Agrippa 
von Nettesheim's praise of "that science divine beyond all human trac- 
ing." In a less degree — for with Apuleius magic is the cult of the 
gods and not much concerned with material things — dt recalls the high 
place assigned to magic by Porta and Francis Bacon. 

1 Bk. i, di. 2 of the life of ApoUonius in the works of Philostratus 
as edited by Gottfridus Olearius. Lipsiae, 1709. dfiiX^aavreg fidyotg koI 
rro?^ daifiSvia elnovreg oiircj iizTjxGrjaav ry T^xyi)* 

2 Indeed " magic," though condemned, was popular, and charlatans 
calling themselves " magi " did a thriving business. 



68 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [68 

have employed the most absurd remedies. Suetonius tdls 
us that the Emperor Augustus wore seal's skin, his suc- 
cessor Tiberius laurel leaves, as a protection against light- 
ning.^ Riny recounts how M. Servilius Nonianus, prittr- 
ceps civitatis, fearing opthalmia, had fastened to his neck 
a piece of linen containing some paper on which were 
written the Greek letters p and a. This was done before 
any mention of the disease was allowed to be made to him 
or by him. Mucianus, thrice consul, carried a live fly 
around in a bit of white linen for a similar purpose, and of 
course both men attributed their escape from disease to 
these bizarre methods.^ Moreover, much magic has been 
supposed to have been involved in the numerous Mysteries 
to which men sought initiation and in the Oriental cults 
which became so popular. Astrology was seemingly as uni- 
versally cultivated as in the Middle Ages, and that, too, 
though perhaps in Roman times it was in appearance less 
of a science and more of a superstition. 

There were occasional imperial edicts against astrologers, 
it is true, and even sporadic persecution of them. But the 
explanation of such measures is belief, not scepticism, and 
they denote not disbelief in the art itself but disapproval of 
the use to which it was put-r-such as revealing the fate of 
the present and the name of the coming ruler. Almost every 
emperor had an astrologer at his court, and the historians 
of the period delighted in telling stories of astrologers who 
foretold their own deaths, or of monarchs who in vain 
attempted to thwart the decrees of fate.^ Alexander Seve- 

1 Suetonius, Aug., ch. xc ; Tiber., ch. Ixix. Cited .by W. E. H. Lecky. 
Hist, of European Morals (London, 1899), vol. i, p. 367. Lecky gives 
a large amount of material on superstition in the Roman Empire. 

^ Nat. Hist., bk. xxviii, ch. 5. 

• A. Bouche Leclercq. " UAstrologie dans le monde romain." Revue 
Histn vol. Ixv, pp. 249 et seq. If ,we may believe the Roman historians. 



69] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 69 

rus IS said to have founded chairs of astrology salaried 
By the state and with provision for scholarships for students.^ 
Occasional persecution perhaps made the mathematici more 
highly valued, and the jibes of the satirists against astrolo- 
gers and their followers attest rather than disprove the 
popularity of the art. Pliny the Elder and Tacitus asserted 
its great currency.^ 

The best science of the Empire reflected to a considerable 
extent these superstitions sanctioned by public opinion, as 
our discussion of Seneca and Ptolemy will indicate in some 
detail. For the present we may observe how the great 
Galen — whose authority reduced to a single school the many 
quarreling medical sects of his day, was later implicitly 
accepted by the Arabs, and then dominated European medi- 
cine to the time of Paracelsus — was not above astrological 
medicine or the use of fantastical remedies. He displayed 
trust in amulets and believed that such things as the ashes 
of frogs or " hippocampi '' have remedial power. ^ He held 
that the critical days of disease are largely influenced by the 
moon, and affirmed that we receive "the force of all the stars 
above." * It should be noted moreover that in one passage, 

Tiberius was a devotee of astrology ; Caligula was warned of his death 
by the stars; Nero, among other acts dictated by his trust in the art, 
ordered a number of executions in order to avoid -the evils threatened 
by a comet; Galba, the three Flavians and Vespasian all had their as- 
trologers; Titus was himself an adept in the art; Domitian, when dis- 
posing of persons whom the sitars designated as dangerous, made the 
fatal error of sparing Nerva because the constellations allowed him 
but a brief additional term of life ; etc, 

^ Revue Hist, vol. Ixv, p. 252. 

2 Nat. Hist., bk. xxx, ch. i, and Tacitus, Annals, bk. vi, ch. 22 (28 in 
some editions). 

^Carolus Gottlob Kuhn. Claudii Galeni Opera Omnia. (Lipsiae, 
1821, 19 vols.), vol. xii, p. 362. De simplicium medicamentorum tem- 
peramentis ac facultatibus. 

^De diebus decretoriis, ibtd,, vol. ix, pp. 901 et seq. irdvruv fih tow 
&V(j6ev aarpuv hiroT^iofi^v rrjg dwdjLiecjg. 



/ 



70 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [70 

in giving expression to his zeal for astronomy as the hand- 
maid of the healing art, Galen accused many physicians of 
paying no attention to the stars. But he asserted that 
in this neglect they were no true followers of the great 
Hippocrates, whom they extolled but never imitated, for 
Hippocrates had maintained that astronomy had no small 
bearing on the art of the physician and that geometry was 
its indispensable precursor.^ 

Philosophy as well as science was not unfavorable to some 
varieties of magic. Neo-Platonism, the most prominent 
school of philosophy in the Empire, probably led men on 
to belief in magic more than any previous classical system. 
Nature was looked upon as real only in so far as it was 
soul, and its process were regarded as the expression of 
the world-soul's mysterious working. The investigation of 
nature thus tended to become an inquiry concerning spirits 
and demons, a study into the strange and subtle relations 
existing between things united, as all things are, by bonds 
of spiritual sympathy. True, the earlier Alexandrines are 
said to have condemned magic arts,^ but we have seen that 
such condemnation need not amount to much. Plotinus 
attacked only the most extreme pretensions of astrology, 
and was ready to grant that the stars were celestial charac- 
ters and signs of the future. He even conceded that predic- 
tion might be made from birds. But to him astrology and 
augury seemed of comparatively small importance, for he 
believed everything to be joined to and dependent upon 
every other thing and that in any object the wise man might 
see signs of everything else.^ Succeeding Neo-Platonists, 

1 " Quod optimus medicus sit quoque philosophus." Ibid., vol. i, p. 53. 

2 Vacherot, L'Ecole d' Alexandria, vol. ii, p. 115. 

'Ricardus Volkmann, Plotini EnneadeSy Lipsiae (Teubner) 1883. 
Ennead ii, ch. iii, sec. 7. oXV ei aij/jLaivovaiv ovtol to, kadfieva^ &aKep 
(jMfjkv TTO/lAa Kal &?i.?ia aijfiavTiKa elvai rav kaofihcjv^ ri av to ttolovv eIij; koI jJ rd^i^ 



71 ] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE yi 

at any rate, were often devoted to magic. The name of 
lamblichus, for instance, is one of the most prominent in 
the field of the occult. 

Moreover, in the time of the Empire a tendency was 
noticeable to confuse philosophy with magic. If this ten- 
dency was not justifiable, it is at least suggestive. Dio 
Cassius, in the passage above quoted, represents Maecenas 
as saying that not a few of those who pretend to be phil- 
osophers practice magic. ^ Apuleius, accused of magic, 
stated in his Apologia that he was undertaking not only his 
own defense but that of philosophy.^ The accusation 
against him also suggests similar charges brought against 
mediaeval men of learning during their lives or reputations 
which they won after death. Apuleius, having married a 
rich widow older than himself, was charged by some syco- 
phant, jealous rival or other personal enemy with having 
obtained her affections by use of sorcery. Apuleius seems 

TTWf ; oh yap av koTffiaivero Terayfiivug (i9} iKdarojv yiyvofiivuv. lara roivw S^airep 
yp&fjLfiaTa kv ovpavc^ ypatpo/ieva ael ^ yeypafifiiva koI tavohfievaj noiovvra juivroi 
ipyov Koi a^lo, eTranoXovdElTD de t^ 6e t) irap' avribv arifjuujia, 6q airh fiidg apx^C kv 
hi ^^9 Trap' blT^v fiipovg &?i'Xo av rig fiddoi, Kal yap not rjdog &v rig yvoirj elg 
IxpddkiwvQ Tivog i6g)v ^ ri dAAo fiipog rov adfiarog nal Kivdhvovg Kal aurijpiag, nal 
ovu fitprj jiev EKelvOf /lipij Sk Kal ijfieig. aXka oiv &X2x)ig, fieard 6i iz&vra aijfieluv 
Kal a(xj>6g rig 6 [laBliv k^ a?[Xov dXAo. izoX^a 6k ^Sjj awi^eig, yiyvdfieva yiv^oKerai 
irdai. Tig ovv 7J ovvra^ig if fiia; ovtcj yap Kal rd Kara rovg 6pveig eiTioyov Kal rd 
&X?ia ^^a, d0' (!)v aTifiaivofi^a EKaara, Gwi^pTfjadai 6^ Set aTXifkoLg to, Tz&vray Kal 
liri fi6vov kv hi TOW Koff EKaara rov ev Eipofihov aifinvota fiiay dAAd nokv fidXXov Kal 
TzpdTEpov kv Tif) navrL This entire third chapter of the Ennead deals with 
the subject, ^rept rdv eI tzoleI to. aarpa. 

See The Philosophy of Plotinus, Dunlap Printing Co., Phila., 1896, 
page 40, for further references to passages in his works giving his 
views anent astrology. He believed that the souls of the dead are 
still able to benefit men and to inspire with powers of divination. 
Ennead, iv, ch. vii, sec. 15. 

^ Page 66, note i. 

2 Apologia, ch. iii. Even if the oration was a satire and not a speech 
actually delivered, the inferences to be drawn from it would be prac- 
tically the same. 



72 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [72 

to have studied medicine, if no other branch of physical 
science, for he asserts that certain verses laid to his charge 
by the accuser deal with nothing more harmful than a recipe 
for making tooth-powder, and that a woman whom he was 
said to have bewitched had merely fallen into an epileptic 
fit while consulting him concerning an ear-ache.^ This 
might be taken to show that the pursuit of science was 
already liable to give one a bad reputation as a wizard ; but 
it should be said that the love-verses of Apuleius, as well as 
his poetical prescriptions, were used to support the accusa- 
tion, and that the purchase of fish was also brought forward 
as a suspicious circumstance. Apuleius affirms in his 01^- 
tion that "philosophers" have always been subjected to such 
charges. He says, however, that the investigators of physical 
causes like Anaxagoras, Leucippus, Democritus and Epi- 
curus generally have the epithet atheist cast in their teeth, 
while it is the seekers into the mysteries of theology and 
religion like Epimenides, Orpheus, Pythagoras and Ostanes 
who are reputed to be magi.^ 

II. Philo of Alexandria and allegorical interpretation. — 
Allegorical interpretation, unless of a very mild character, 
is usually a fantastic and mystical method of deriving in- 
formation or inspiration. Even if an author intended to 
conceal secret mysteries beneath the letter of his text, there 

^ Apuleius may have been guilty of attempting to practice magic. Cer- 
tainly he 'believed in its possibility. He affirmed the existence of subor- 
dinate gods, or demons, — ^interpreters and aittbassadors between mankind 
and the superior gods, who live far away from us and have no direct 
concern with our affairs. The demons, he believed, were susceptible 
to human influence and capable of working marvels. He stated that 
the art of divination was due to them. See his De Deo Socratis. 

2 Apologia^ ch. xxvii. Evidently hostility to magic did not commence 
with Christianity. Not even, as Roger Bacon thought, did the practice 
of confusing philosophy with magic originate among Christian writers. 
Bridges, Opus Mains, vol. i, p. 29. 



73] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 73 

IS very slight chance that the far-fetched and intricate mode 
of solution employed by the interpreter will be the one 
which the writer had in mind. In most cases, however, 
after due allowance has been made for figures of speech 
and play of poetical imagination, it is an erroneous and 
absurd assumption to suppose that an author did not mean 
what his language indicates and no more. Therefore the 
believer in allegorical interpretation would seem to be ac- 
cepting something quite like a magical doctrine. Indeed, 
allegorical interpretation is liable to lead one into a belief 
that words, besides possessing a mystical significance with 
which the thought of their writer had endowed them, have 
in and of themselves great power. It borders upon the 
occult reveries of the Cabalists and upon that magic power 
of words which we have seen upheld by Roger Bacon, John 
Reuchlin and Henry Cornelius Agrippa. 

This allegorical interpretation of literature has played a 
great part in human history. It was rife in the age of the 
Roman Empire, when Philo Judaeus of Alexandria (ap- 
proximate date, 30 B. c. to 54 a. d.) was perhaps its great- 
est exponent, as he was also the chief member of the Jewish- 
Alexandrian school of philosophy. 

Philo carried allegorical interpretation to an absurd ex- 
treme even if he did not go quite so far as Reuchlin and 
Agrippa. Not only did he make such assertions as that by 
Hagar was typified " encyclical education," that Ishmael 
was her " sophist son," and that Sarah stood for " the rul- 
ing virtue," ^ but in general he tried to read into the Old 

^ See Philo's treatise De Cherubim, cited in vol. ii, p. 243, of Rev. 
James Drummond's Philo Judaeus; or The Jewish Alexandrian Philo- 
sophy in its Development and Completion (2 vols., London, 1888). 
Concerning Philo see also Edouard Harriot, Philon le Juif (Fslt'is, 1898), 
where a full bioliography of Philonian and Jewish-Alexandrian litera- 
ture may be found. A third important secondary book on Philo is by 
Siegfried: Philo von Alexandria (Jena, 1875). 



74 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [74 

Testament all the doctrines of Greek philosophy and science. 
He declared that all knowledge, whether in religfion, phil- 
osophy or natural science, might be acquired by all^orical 
interpretation of the Pentateuch. Now we can say without 
manifesting any semblance of irreverence towards true re- 
ligion, that to endeavor to gain from the books of the Old 
Testament — especially by the methods which Philo employed 
— either the key to all philosophy or adequate knowledge of 
natural science and extensive control of the forces of nature, 
would, if possible, be as marvelous a feat, and is as falla- 
cious and fantastic a proceeding, as to try to coin gold from 
copper, or to learn the future from the stars, or even to 
obtain a solution of the problems of philosophy and a 
knowledge and control of nature by invoking demons to in- 
struct and to assist you. The very notion that some man 
like Moses a thousand or more years ago had at his com- 
mand all the knowledge that can ever be got is magical itself. 
Moses must have been a magician to know so much. Philo, 
moreover, if he did not believe in a magic power of words, 
at least showed that they seemed to him to have a most 
extraordinary significance. In his treatise, De Mutatione 
Nominum, he relates with great unction the just punish- 
ment of hanging which overtook an impious scoffer who 
derided the notion that the change in the names of Abraham 
and of Sarah had any profound meaning.^ As one would 
naturally expect from what has been said about Philo thus 
far, he regarded knowledge as something sacred and eso- 
teric. In his writings he liked to talk of mysteries and to 
request the uninitiated to withdraw. This attitude, while 
in itself not exactly magic, is,^ as has been already suggested, 
the product of a mind attuned to magic. Finally, Philo, fol- 
lowing Pythagoras, attached great significance to numbers. 

1 Drummond, vol. i, p. 13. 



75] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 75 

Philo not only represents a widespread tendency during 
the Roman Empire, but probably well illustrates the influ- 
ence of that tendency upon later times. His numerous 
works were apparently much consulted by the church 
fathers, and thereby exerted a strong influence upon the 
Middle Ages. It is needless to enlarge upon the promi- 
nence of allegorical interpretation in the works of mediaeval 
ecclesiastical writers. The conception of knowledge as 
esoteric was also prevalent then, though perhaps to a less 
extent. To give an early instance from patristic literature, 
Clement of Alexandria, in his Stromata, insists upon the 
necessity of veiling divine truth in allegories, and has a 
long discussion in favor of mysticism in learning, citing as 
examples Greek philosophers as well as Hebrew writers.^ 
Moreover, to Philo as source we may trace back the dis- 
quisitions upon the mystic, if not magic, properties of six and 
other numbers which we find in Augustine ^ and apparently 
in almost every mediaeval writer who had occasion to speak 
of the six days of creation and of the seventh day of rest. 

ni. Senecds Problems of Nature and divination, — We 
shall next consider the Problems of Nature — or Natural 
Questions, if one prefers merely to transcribe the Latin — 
of Seneca, who was practically a contemporary of Pliny. 
Seneca impresses one as a favorable representative of an- 
cient science. He tells us that already in his youth he had 
written a treatise on earthquakes and their causes.® His 

^ Stromata, bk. v, ch. 9. Nor was such mysticism advocated by theo- 
logical writers alone. Roger Bacon — but one instance from many — 
declared that one lessened the majesty of knowledge who divulged its 
mysteries, and even went to the length of enumerating seven methods 
by which the arcana of philosophy and science might be concealed from 
the crowd (a vulgo), De Secretis Artis et Naturae et de Nullitate 
Magiae. Rolls Series, vol. xv, pp. 543-544. 

2 De Civitate Dei, bk. xi, ch. 30. 

8 " Aliquando De Motu Terrarum volumen iuvenis ediderim." L. 



76 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [76 

aim is to inquire into the natural causes of phenomena; he 
wants to know why things are so. He is aware that his 
own age has only entered the vestibule of the knowledge 
of natural phenomena and forces, that it has but just begun 
to know five of the many stars, that " there will come a 
time when our descendants will wonder that we were ignor- 
ant of matters so evident/' ^ 

One must admit, however, that along with Seneca's con- 
sciousness of the very imperfect knowledge of his own age 
there goes a tendency to esotericism. The following lan- 
guage would come fittingly from the mouth of a magician : 

There are sacred things which are not revealed all at once. 
Eleusis reserves sights for those who revisit her. Nature does 
not disclose her mysteries in a moment. We think ourselves 
initiated ; we stand but at her portal. Those secrets open not 
promiscuously nor to every comer. They are remote of access, 
enshrined in the inner sanctuary.^ 

Seneca seems to regard scientific research as a sort of re- 
ligious exercise. His enthusiasm in the study of natural 
forces appears largely due to the fact that he believes them 
to be of a sublime and divine character, and above the petty 
affairs of men. 

Aiinaei Seneoae Naturalium QuaesHonum Libri Septemj bk. vi, ch. 4. 
The edition by G, D. Koeler, Gottitigen, 1819 has convenient summaries 
indicating contents at the head of each 'book, and devotes several hun- 
dred pages to a " Disquisitio " and " Animadversiones " upon Seneca's 
work. In Pancoucke's Library, vol. cxxxxvii, a French translation ac- 
companies the text. 

1 " Veniet tempus, quo posteri nostri tarn aperta nos nescisse mirentur. 
Harimi quinque stellarum . . . modo ooepimus scire." Bk. vii, ch. 25. 

2 Bk. vii, ch. 31. " Non semel quaedam sacra traduntur. Eleusin 
servat quod ostendit revisentibus. Rerum natura sacra sua non simul 
tradit. Initiatos nos credimus ; in vestibule eius haeremus. Ilia arcana 
non promiscue nee omnibus patent; reducta et in interiore sacrario 
clausa sunt." 



./^ 



yy^ BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE yy 

Indeed, the phenomena which he discusses are mainly 
meteorological manifestations, such as winds, rain, hail, 
snow, comets, rainbows, and — what he regards as allied sub- 
jects — earthquakes, springs and rivers. Probably he would 
not have regarded the study of zoology or of physiology as 
so sublime. At any rate he considers only a comparatively 
few " natural questions," and hence the amount and variety 
of belief in magic which he has occasion to display is cor- 
respondingly limited. 

It is evident enough, however, that Seneca by no means 
accepted magic as a whole. He tells us that uncivilized 
antiquity believed that rain could be brought on or driven 
away by incantations, but that to-day no one needs a phil- 
osopher to teach him that this is impossible.^ And, al- 
though he affirms that living beings are generated in fire, 
believes in some rather peculiar effects of lightning, such 
as removing the venom from- snakes which it strikes, and 
recounts the old stories of floating islands and of waters 
with power to turn white sheep black, he is sceptical about 
bathing in the waters of the Nile as a means of increasing 
the female's capacity for child-bearing.^ He qualifies by 
the phrases, " it is believed " and " they say,** the asser- 
tions that certain waters produce foul skin-diseases and that 
dew in particular, if collected in any quantity, has this evil 
property.* I imagine he did not believe the story he re- 
peats that the river Alphaeus of Greece reappears in Sicily 

1 Bk. iv, ch. 7. " Et apud nos in duodecim tabulis cavetur ne quis 
alienos fructus excantassit. Rudis adhuc antiquitas credebat et attrahi 
imbres cantibus, et repelli; quorum nihil posse fieri, tam palam est, ut 
huius rei causa nullius philosophi schola intranda sit." 

2 Bk. V, ch. 6 for animals being generated in flames. 
Bk. ii, ch. 31 for snakes struck by lightning. 

Bk. iii, ch. 25 for the Nile. Bk. iii passim, for marvelous fountains, etc, 

8 Bk. iii, ch. 25. 



78 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [78 

as the Arethusa, and there every four years, on the very- 
days when the victims are slaughtered at the Olympian 
games, casts up filth from its depths.^ The themes Seneca 
discusses of course afford him less opportunity for the tak- 
ing up of the magic properties of plants, animals and other 
objects, but he was probably less credulous in this respect 
than Pliny, unless his pretensions are even more deceptive. 
Seneca did believe, however, that whatever is caused is 
a sign of some future event.^ He accepts divination in all 
its ramifications. Only he holds that each flight of a bird 
is not caused by direct act of God nor the vitals of the 
victim altered under the axe by divine interference, but 
that all has been arranged beforehand in a fatal and causal 
■ series.* He believes that all unusual celestial phenomena 
are to be looked upon as prodigies and portents.* But no 
\ less truly do the planets in their unvarying courses signify 
the future. The stars are of divine nature and we ought 
to approach the discussion of them with as reverent an air 
as when with lowered countenance we enter the temples for 
worship.*^ Not only do the stars influence our upper atmos- 
phere as earth's exhalations affect the lower, but they an- 
nounce what is to occur.® Seneca employs the statement of 
Aristotle that comets signify the coming of storms and 
winds and foul weather, to prove that comets are stars; 

^ Bk. idi, ch. 26. 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 32. " Quidquid fit, alicuius rei futurae signum est." 

8 Bk. ii, ch. 46. * Bk. i, ch. i. 

*^ Bk. vii, ch. 30. " Egregie Aristoteles ait, numquam nos verecun- 
diorcs esse debere, quam quum de diis agitur. Si intramus templa com- 
positi, si ad sacrificium accesuri vultum submittimus, togam adducimus, 
si in omne argumentum modestiae fingimur ; quanto hoc magis f acere de- 
bemus, quum de sideribus, de stellis, de deorum natura disputamus, ne 
quid temere, ne quid impudenter, aut ignorantes affirmemus, aut 
scientes mentiamur?" 

« Bk. ii, ch. 10. 



\ 



79] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 79 

and declares that a comet is a portent of a storm in the 
same way as the Chaldeans say that a star brings good or 
ill fate to men at birth. ^ In fact, his chief, if not sole, ob- 
jection to the Chaldeans would seem to be that in their pre- 
dictions they take into account only five stars. 

What? Think you so many thousand stars shine on in vain? 
What else, indeed, is it which causes those skilled in nativities 
to err than that they assign us to a few stars, although all those 
that are above us have a share in the control of our fate? 
Perhaps those nearer direct their influence upon us more \ 

closely; perhaps those of more rapid motion look down on us 
and other animals from more varied aspects. But even those 
stars that are motionless, or because of their speed keep equal 
pace with the rest of the universe and seem not to move, are 
not without rule and dominion over us.^ 

Seneca accepts a theory of Berosus, whose acquaintance we 
have already made, that whenever all the stars are in con- 
junction in the sign of Cancer there will be a universal 
conflagration, and a second deluge when they all unite in 
Capricorn.* 

It is on thunderbolts as portents of the future that Seneca 
dwells longest, however. " They give," he declares, " not 

^ Bk. vii, 28. " Chaldean " was often used to denote an astrologer 
without reference to the person's nationality. 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 32. " Qtdnque stellarum potestatem Chaidaeorum obser- 
vatio excepit. Quid tu? tot millia siderum judicas otiosa lucere? Quid 
est porro aliud, quod errorem incutiat peritis natalium, quam quod paucis 
nos sideribus assignant: quum omnia quae supra nos sunt, partem sibi 
nostri vindicent? Submissiora forsitan in nos propius vim suam diri- 
gunt; et ea quae frequentius mota aliter nos, aliter cetera animalia 
prospiciunt. Ceterum et ilia quae auit immota sunt, aut propter velo- 
citatem universo mundo parem immotis similia, non extra ius dominium- 
que nostri sunt. Aliud aspice et distributis rem officiis tractas. Non 
magis autem facile est scire quid possint, quam dubitari debet, an 
possint." 

8 Bk. iii, ch. 29. 



/ 
f •■ 



8o MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [go 

signs of this or that event merely, but often announce a 
whole series of events destined to occur, and that by mani- 
fest decrees and ones far clearer than if they were set down 
in writing." ^ He will not, however, accept the theory that 
lightning has such great power that its intervention nullifies 
any previous and contradictory portents. He insists that 
divination by other methods is of equal truth, though per- 
haps of minor importance and significance. Next he at- 
tempts to explain how dangers of which we are warned by 
divination may be averted by prayer, expiation or sacrifice, 
and yet the chain of events wrought by destiny not be 
broken. He maintains that just as we employ the services 
of doctors to preserve our health, despite any belief we may 
have in fate, so it is useful to consult a haritspex. Then he 
goes on to speak of various classifications of thunderbolts 
according to the nature of the warnings or encouragements 
which they bring.^ 

IV. Ptolemy's Tetrabiblos and astrology. — ^Astrology was 
more than a popular belief which extended to men high in 
social rank and public life; it was held by scientists as well, 
though naturally in a less naive and more scientific form. 
Nevertheless, the astrology of the scientist might be of an 
extreme enough type and of a more clearly magical variety 
than we were able to gather from Pliny, who, moreover, 
does not seem to have been acquainted with any systematic 
doctrine of the influence of the stars. 

Such a systematized treatment Claudius Ptolemaeus set 

^ Bk. ii, ch. 32. Seneca has been describing other manifestations of 
the "divina et subtilis potentia" of thunderbolts; he proceeds, "Quid, 
quod futura portendunt: nee unius tantum aut alterius rei signa dant, 
sed saepe totum fatorum sequentium ordinem nuntiant, et quidem de- 
cretis evidentibus, longeque clarioribus, quam si scriberentur ?*' 

2 His discussion of divination by thunderbolts is contained in 
bk. ii, ch. 31-50. 



8i] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE gl 

forth in the little volume known as the Tetrabiblos, or 
Quddripartitum. It would seem as if we ought to be able 
to regard a book by that noted geographer and astronomer 
as an example of the best science of his time, the middle of 
the second century. His works quickly became classics, and 
in the third century Porphyry commented on the Tetrabiblos. 
The Ara:bs eagerly accepted his writings, and it is generally 
held that in the Middle Ages his word was law in all the 
subjects of which he treated. The Tetrabiblos, therefore, 
would seem a landmark in the entire history of astrology 
as well as a crucial instance of how that branch of magic 
formed a part of science in the Roman Empire. True, 
Ptolemy does not cover the whole field of sidereal influence. 
He limits himself to the effects of the stars on man and 
does not attempt to trace out how they affect all varieties 
of matter and of life upon our globe. However, to make 
the stars control each individual man is the climax of 
astrology and implies that the heavenly bodies govern every- 
thing else here on earth. So the Tetrabiblos is a very satis- 
factory instance of belief in astrology by a scientist and its 
contents may well be briefly considered.^ 

The first of the four books opens with the trite conten- 
tion that the art itself is not to be rejected because fre- 

1 The edition of the Tetrabiblos which I used is that by Philip 
Melanchthon, 1553. It gives the Greek text, a Latin translation and an 
introduction of interest, in which Melanchthon affirms his own more 
modest trust in astrology. 

Two other treatises of considerable length setting forth the prin- 
ciples of astrology and which have come down to us from the Roman 
Empire, are a poem consisting of five books of about 900 lines each by 
Manilius, probably of the Augustan age; and' a prose treatise in eight 
books, and apparently left unfinished, by Firmicus who was a Neo- 
Platonist of about 350 a. d. M. Manilii Astronomicon, London, 1828, 
Delphin edition. lulii Firmici Matemd Matheseos Libri VIII, (edider- 
unt W. KroU et K Skutsch, Lipsiae, 1897, 2 vols., (Teubner edition). 
The essay on astrology purporting to be by Lucian is probably spurious. 



82 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 

quently abused by imposters, and with the admission that 
even the skilful investigator often makes mistakes owing to 
the incompleteness of human knowledge. In the first place, 
our doctrine of the nature of matter rests, Ptolemy says, more 
on conjecture than on certain knowledge. Secondly, old con- 
figurations of the stars cannot be safely used as the basis of 
present-day predictions. Indeed, so many are the different 
possible positions of the stars and the different possible 
arrangements of terrestrial matter in relation to the stars 
that it is difficult to collect enough instances on which to 
base judgment. Moreover, such things as diversity of place, 
of education and of custom must be reckoned with in fore- 
telling the future of persons bom under the same stars. 
But although predictions frequently fail, yet the art is not 
to be condemned any more than one rejects the art of navi- 
gation because of frequent shipwrecks. 

Thus far one might take Ptolemy for a well-balanced and 
accurate scientist in the modern sense of the term, but he 
does not maintain this level. After showing that it is use- 
ful to know the future and that astrology does not depend 
on fatal necessity, he proceeds to explain why the stars give 
knowledge of the future. This he intends to show from 
natural causes: iibique naturalium causarum rationem se- 
quentes. This sounds well but his reasoning is superficial 
and childish, as his discussion of the influence exercised by 
che planets will indicate. 

In each planet one of the four elemental qualities pre- 
dominates (or perhaps two divide the supremacy) and en- 
dows the star with a peculiar nature and power. The sun 
warms and, to some extent, makes dry, for the nearer it 
comes to our pole the more heat and drought it produces. 
The moon, on the contrary, causes humidity, since it is 
close to the earth and gets the effect of vapors from 
the latter. Evidently the moon influences other bodies 



83] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 83 

in this way, rendering them soft and producing putrefac- 
tion. It also warms a little owing to the light it receives 
from the sun. Saturn, however-, chills and, to some extent, 
dries, for it is very far from the heat of the sun and the 
damp mists of the earth. Mars emits a parching heat, 
as its color and proximity to the sun lead one to infer. 
Jupiter, situated between cold Saturn and burning Mars, is 
of a sort of lukewarm nature, but tends more to warmth 
and moisture than to the other two qualities. So does 
Venus, but conversely, for it warms less than Jupiter but 
makes moist more, since its large area catches many damp 
vapors from the neighboring earth. In Mercury, situated 
near the sun, moon and earth, neither drought nor damp- 
ness predominates ; but that planet, incited by its own veloc- 
ity, is a potent cause of sudden changes. In general, the 
planets are of good or evil influence according as they 
abound in the two rich and vivifying qualities, heat and 
moisture, or in the detrimental and destructive ones, cold 
and drought. 

Ptolemy then goes on to discuss the powers of fixed stars. 
These powers he would seem to make depend chiefly on the 
relation of the fixed star to the planets or on its position in 
some constellation. Then he treats of the influence of the 
seasons and of the four cardinal points, to each of 
which he assigns some one predominating quality. A 
discussion of the importance of such things as the twelve 
signs of the zodiac, the twelve " houses," the Trigones 
(equilateral triangles each comprising three signs of the 
zodiac), and the position of the star in reference to the 
horizon, ends the first book and also the presentation of 
fundamental considerations. 

The other three books contain "doctrinam de praedictione 
singnlarium." The second book, however, deals in the 
main with four points of general though subordinate bear- 



84 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [84 

ing: under what stars different regions belong, how the 
effects of the stars vary according to time as well as place, 
how the heavenly bodies influence the nature of events, and 
finally how they determine their quality, good or bad. The 
third and fourth books, besides taking up separately the 
particular effects of each planet as it enters into conjunction 
with each of the others, comprise chapters with such head- 
ings as the following: " de parentibus/' " de fratribtis/^ 
'' de masculis et femellis," '' de geminis/' '' de natis qtd 
nutrire non possunt sed mox extinguuntur" " de dignitate" 
'' de magisterio/' " de coniugiis/' " de liberis/' " de amicis 
et inimicis" " de servisl' " de perigrinatione," '' de genere 
mortis." These two books discuss how length of years, for- 
tune, diseases, and various qualities of body and mind may 
be predicted from the stars ; in short, how man's entire life 
is ordered by the constellations. Such is the book which 
Bouche-Leclercq calls " science's surrender." ^ 

V. The hermetic books and occultism. — An account of 
belief in magic in the Roman Empire would be incomplete 
without some reference to the famous hermetic books. 
Hermes Trismegistus might, as deservedly as any other 
man — had he only been a man and not a myth — ^be called 
the father of magic, just as he used to be known as the 
father of Egyptian science and just as he was r^arded by 
many as the inventor of all philosophy.^ In the time of 
Plato the Egyptian god Thoth acquired the name of Her- 
mes from the similarity of his functions to those of the 
Greek god. He also came to be considered as the author 
of pretty much all knowledge and was given the epithet of 
" Thrice Great." The entire body of Egyptian occult lore 

1 " Cetait la capitulaition de la science." Rev. Hist, vol. Ixv, /p. 257, 
note 3. 

2 Roger Bacon, Opus Minus, Rolls Series, vol. xv, p. 313, speaks of 
"Hermes Mercurius, pater philosophorum." 



85] BELIEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 85 

was attributed to him, and Manetho, who pictured him as 
reigning over the ancient Egyptians, declared tliat in addi- 
tion to his royal duties he succeeded in turning oflf some 
36,000 volumes. Clement of Alexandria, however, speaks 
of but forty-two books as " indispensably necessary," and 
says that the priests having charge of the hermetic books, 
by memorizing these forty-two, cover the entire philosophy 
of the Egyptians.^ Diocletian is said to have dispersed the 
priests and burned their books, because he came to the con- 
clusion that the frequent revolts in the locality received 
pecuniary aid by means of gold artificially manufactured 
in the temples.^ Before that, however, lore supposed 
to be similar to that contained within the books had be- 
come disseminated. In the days of Hadrian and the An- 
tonines, Jews and other Orientals at Rome offered to initiate 
persons into those occult sciences previously the monopoly 
of the Egyptian priesthood. Marcus Aurelius, in his later 
years, was thus instructed by an E^ptian diviner, who fol- 
lowed him in all his campaigns.' Also the custom grew 
up rather early of passing off works on occult subjects 
under Hermes' name and of ascribing to him all such books 
which were of doubtful authorship. Of alchemy was this 
tendency especially true, so that it came to be known as the 
hermetic art. Sosimus, Stephanus and other Greek writers 
cited alchemical treatises under Hermes' name, and the prac- 
tice of publishing spurious hermetic books continued well into 

1 Stromata, ,bk. vi, ch. 4. 

2 Ammianus Marcellinus, 'however, writing during the latter fourth 
century, says of Egypt : " Hie primum homines longe ante alios ad varia 
religionum incunabula, ut dicitur, pervenerunt et initia prima sacrorum 
caute tuentur condita scriptis arcanis." Bk. xxii, ch. xvi, sec. 20, 
Again, in bk. xxii, ch. xiv, sec. 7, Ammianus speaks of the Egyptian 
mystical books as still extant. 

8 F. J. Champagny, Les AntoninSy vol. iii, p. 81 (Paris, 1863). 



86 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [86 

the Middle Ages.^ Several such alchemical treatises are 
still extant; and writings on astrological medicine and the 
magical powers of gems, plants and animals have also come 
down to us tmder Hermes' name.* 

Some of the supposed writings of Hermes were mystical 
rather than magical; for instance, the famous Poemander* 
which consists mainly of brief and disconnected utterances 
concerning God and the human soul and other subjects of 
a religious character. Still, one does not have to read far 
into its sixteen "books" before finding evidence of belief in 
astrology, of the mysticism of number and of an esoteric view 
of knowledge. It tells us " to avoid all conversation with 
the multitude " and to " take heed of them as not tmder- 
standing the virtue and power of the things that are said." 
It speaks frequently of the seven circles of heaven, the seven 
zones, and the seven " Governors." It affirms that " the 

1 See article on " Hermes " in La Grande Encyclopidie by Berthelot 
wiho has made an exten-ded study of the history of aldhemy; and who, 
in his La Chitnie au Moyen Age holds that Greek alchemistic treat- 
ises were continuously extant in Italy during the Dark Ages — a cir- 
cumstance which diminishes the importance of Arabian influence on 
the study of the hermetic art in tflie later Middle Ages. 

2 See Anthonys Classical Dictionary^ 1855 (no adequate account of 
Hermes Trismegistus exists in any of the more recent classical diction- 
aries). 

8 The Poemander (or Pymander) has been reproduced in the Bath 
Occult Reprint Series (London, 1884) from the translation "from 
the Arabic by Dr. Everard, 1650." It has an introduction by Hargrave 
Jennings, " author of the Rosicrucians," giving some account of Hermes 
Trismegistus. Vol. ii in the same Bath Occult Reprint Series — which 
seems to have been instituted on behalf of "students of the occult 
sciences, searchers after truth and Theosophists " — is Hermes' Virgin 
of the World. Besides Berthelofs article, an account of Hermes may 
be found in pages 181-190 of The Literary Remains of the late Eman- 
uel Deutsch (London, 1879). There is a French translation of the 
Poemander by Menard with an introductory essay which, however, 
Deutsdh characterized as "deploraibly shallow." 



87] BEUEF IN MAGIC IN THE EMPIRE 87 

Gods were seen in their Ideas of the Stars with all their 
signs, and the stars were numbered with the Gods in 
them." Hence, it is probably safe enough, when, for in- 
stance, we hear that Theon, father of Hypatia, celebrated in 
his day as a mathematician, and professor at the Alexan- 
drian Museum, lectured upon the writings of Hermes Tris- 
m^stus and of Orpheus ^ — another legendary worthy 
charged with works of an occult character — to conclude 
that we have met one more case of the mingling of magic 
with learning. 

In short, then, the mythical figure of Hermes Trismegis- 
tus became an actuating ideal to the Middle Ages, and the 
works appearing imder his name had a considerable influ- 
ence in extending belief in magic. Secondly, the hermetic 
books serve to typify that mass of Eastern occult philosophy 
and occult science which was so strong a force in the mental 
life of the Roman En^pire. 

1 J. B. Bury, Later Roman Empire (N. Y., 1899), vol. i, p. 208. 



CHAPTER VI 

Critics of Magic 

The reader will remember how men in the Roman Em- 
pire condemned " magic " but understood the word in a 
restricted and bad sense; how Pliny made pretensions to 
complete freedom from all belief in magic and how incon- 
sistent was his actual attitude; how Seneca rejected magic 
only in part, accepting divination in all its ramifications. 
This partial rejection and partial acceptance of magic by 
the same individual seem characteristic of the age of the 
Empire, as one would expect of a time when magic was in 
a state of decay and science in a process of development. 
It is true that this rejection of certain varieties of magic 
often proceeded from the motive of morality rather than of 
scepticism. Thus in Cicero's De Divinatione, Quintus 
Cicero is represented as closing his long argument in favor 
of the truth of divination by solemnly asserting that he 
does not approve of sorcerers, nor of those who prophesy 
for sake of gain, nor of the practice of questioning spirits 
of the dead — which nevertheless, he says, was a custom of 
his brother's friend Appius.^ But there were some men, 
we may well believe, who would reject even those varieties 
of magic which found a welcome in the minds of most edu- 
cated people and in the general mass of the thought and 
science of the age. Such cases we shall now consider. 

^ De Dimnatione, bk. i, ch. 58. "Haec habui, inquit, de divinatione 
quae dicerem. Nunc ilia testabor non me sortilegos neque eos qui qua- 
estus causa hariolentur, ne psychomantia quidem quibus Appius amicus 
tuus uti solebat, agnoscere." 

88 [88 



89] CRITICS OF MAGIC 89 

I. Opponents of astrology. — ^Astrology, as we have seen, 
was very popular. Yet there was some scepticism as to its 
truth beyond the ridicule of satirists, who perhaps at bot- 
tom were themselves believers in the art. Outside of Chris- 
tian writers the three chief opponents of astrology in the 
Roman world, judging by the works that have come down 
to us, were Cicero — who lived before the Empire in the 
constitutional sense can be said to have begun — in his De 
Diznnatione ; Favorinus, a Gaul who resided at Rome in the 
reigns of Hadrian and Trajan, and was a friend of Plu- 
tarch, and whose arguments against astrology have been 
preserved only in the pages of Aulus GelHus; and Sextus 
Empiricus, a physician who flourished at about the begin- 
ning of the third century of our era.^ 

When, however, we come to examine both the men and 
their arguments, we somehow do not find their assault upon 
astrology especially impressive or satisfactory. First, as to 
the men. Gellius says that he heard Favorinus make the 
speech the substance of which he repeats, but that he is un- 
able to state whether the philosopher really meant what he 
said or argued merely in order to exercise and to display 
his genius.^ There was reason for this perplexity of Gel- 

1 For the arguments of Favorinus, see Aulus Gellius, Nodes Atticae, 
bk. xiv; ch. i. (Delphin & Variorum Classics [1824] ex editione Jacohi 
Gronovii.) Fragments of Favorinus's writings are also to be found in 
Stobaeus. 

The edition of the Opera of Sextus Empiricus which I used was 
that by Johannes Albertus Fabricus, (Lipsiae, 1718), giving the Greek 
text and a Latin translation. 

For Cicero's arguments, see De Divinatione, bk. ii, chs. 42-47. 

2 " Adversum istos qui sese chaldaeos seu genethliacos appellant, ac 
de motu deque positu stellarum dicere posse, quae futura sunt, pro- 
fitentur, audivimus quondam Favorinum philosophum Romae Graecc 
disserentem egregia atque illustri oratione; exercendine autcm, anne 
ostentandi gratia ingenii, an quod ita serio judicatoque existamarct, non 
habeo dicere. Nodes Atticae, bk. xiv, ch. i, sect. i. A foot-note in the 



go MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [90 

lius, since Favorinus was fond of writing such essays as 
Eulogies of Thersites and of Quartan Fever. There is no 
particular reason for doubting Sextus's seriousness, but, be- 
sides being a medical man, he was a member of the sceptical 
school of philosophy, a circumstance which warns one not 
to attribute too much emphasis to his attack on astrology. 
Indeed, the attack occurs in a work directed against learn- 
ing in general, in which he assails grammarians, rhetor- 
icians, geometricians, arithmeticians, students of music, 
logicians, "physicists," and students of ethics as well as 
astrologers. Cicero was not prone to such sweeping scep- 
ticism or sophistry, but the force of his opposition to astrol- 
ogy is somewhat neutralized by the fact that in his Dream 
of Scipio he apparently attributes to planets influence over 
man. 

Now as to their arguments. We have spoken of their 
" attack on astrology,'' but in reality they can scarcely be 
said to attack astrology as a whole. Indeed, it is the doc- 
trines of the Chaldeans which Cicero makes the object of 
his assault; he says nothing about astrology. Favorinus 
will not even admit that he attacks the " disciplina Chal- 
daeorum " in any true sense, but affirms that the Chaldeans 
were not the authors of such theories at all, but that these 
have originated of late among traveling fakirs who beg 
their bread by means of such deceits and trickeries.^ Some 
of the arguments of our sceptics are really directed merely 

Delphin edition expresses preference in place af the words "exer- 
cendine autein, anne ostentendi" for the shorter reading "exercendi 
autem, non ostentandi" — which reading is adopted by Hertz in his 
edition of the year, 1885. 

1 " Disciplinam istam Chaldaeorum tantae vetustatis non esse, quantae 
videri volunt; neque eos principes eius auctoresque esse, quos ipsi fer- 
ant: sed id praestigiarum atque offuciarum genus commentos esse 
homines aeruscatores, et cibum quaestumque ex mendaciis captantes." 
Nodes Atticae, bk. xiv, ch. i, sect. 2. 



.^^1* 



gi] CRITICS OF MAGIC 91 

against the methods of interpreting the decrees of the stars 
which they give us to understand that the astrologers employ. 
Such objections might suffice to pierce the presumption of 
the ordinary popular astrologer but they fall back blunted 
from the system of Ptolemy/ If our sceptics thought that 
they were overthrowing the astrology of the man of learn- 
ing by such arguments, they labored under a misapprehen- 
sion, and in the eyes of one who really imderstood the art 
must have cut the figure of ignoramuses making false 
charges against a science of which they knew next to 
nothing. 

As some of the arguments of our sceptics apply solely to 
defects in method of which the best astrologers were not 
guilty, so others do not deny the existence of sidereal influ- 
ence over the life of man, but contend that it is impossible 
to determine with essential accuracy what will be the effects 
of that influence. Sextus, for example, seems to lay most 
stress upon such points as the difficulty of exactly determin- 
ing the date of birth or of conception, or the precise moment 
when a star passes into a new sign of the zodiac. He calls 
attention to the fact that observers at varying altitudes, as 
well as in different localities, would arrive at different con- 
clusions, that differences in eyesight would also affect re- 
sults, and that it is hard to tell just when the sun sets owing 

^ For mstance, the charge that astrologers disr^ard the diflFering 
aspects of the heavens in diflFerent regions does not hold true in the 
case of Ptolemy. Also the objection to the doctrine of nativities, that 
men born at different times often suffer a common fate in battle or 
some such general disaster, is a weak argument at best, for the 
fact that you and I are born under different stars does not necessitate 
that our careers have absolutely nothing in common, and it was nulli- 
fied by Ptolemy's explanation that great general events like earth- 
quakes, wars, floods and plagues overrule any contradictory destiny 
which the constellations may seem to portend for the individual. See 
Bouche-Leclerq, Rev. Hist, vol. Ixv, p. 268. 



92 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [92 

to refraction/ He almost becomes scholastic in the minute- 
ness of his objections, leaving us somewhat in doubt whether 
they are to be taken as indicative of a spirit of captious 
criticism towards an art the fundamental principles of which 
he tacitly recognized as well-nigh incontestible, or whether 
he is simply trying to make his case doubly sure by showing 
astrology to be impracticable as well as unreasonable. 

The main thing to be noted about Cicero, Favorinus and 
Sextus is that they pay almost no attention to the general 
problem of sidereal influence on terrestrial matter and life. 
It is to the denial of an absolute, complete and immutable 
rule of the heavenly bodies over man that they devote their 
energies. The premises of astrology they leave pretty much 
alone. One might accept almost all their statements and 
still believe in a large influence of the stars over our physi- 
cal characteristics and mental traits. The question of 
sidereal influence upon lower animal life, vegetation and 
inert matter they avoid with a sneer. ^ 

1 Similarly Favorinus declared that, if the diflFerent fate of twins 
was to he explained hy the fact that after all they are not horft at 
precisely the same moment, then to determine one's -destiny the time 
of his birth and the position of the stars at the same instant must be 
measured with an exactness practically impossible. "A/tque id velim 
etiam, inquit, ut respondeant: si tam parvum atque rapidum est mo- 
mentum temporis, in quo homo nascens fatum accipit, ut in eodem illo 
puncto, sub eodem circulo coeli, plures simul ad eamdem competentiam 
nasci non queant; et si idcirco gemini quoque non eadem vitae sorte 
sunt, quoniam non eodem temporis puncto editi sunt; peto, inquit, re- 
spondeant, cursum ilium temporis transvolantis, qui vix cogitatione animi 
comprehendi potest, quonam pacto aut consulto assequi queant, aut ipsi 
perspicere et deprehendere ; quum in tam praecipiti dierum noctiumque 
vertigine minima momenta ingentes facere dicant mutationes." Nodes 
AtticaCf bk. xiv, ch. i, sect. 10. 

2 Favorinus declares that the astrologers may congratulate them- 
selves that he does not propose such a question to them as that 
of astral influence on minute animals; Cicero says that if all animals 



^3] CRITICS OF MAGIC 93 

II. Cicero's attack upon divination, — ^A more satisfactory 
example of scepticism may be found in other chapters of 
the De Divinatione than those which assail the art of the 
Chaldeans. Moreover, although the discussion is limited 
to the specific theme of divination, still that is a subject 
which admits of very broad interpretation, and Cicero em- 
ploys some arguments which are capable of an even wider 
application and oppose the hypotheses on which magic in 
general rests. He rejects divination as unscientific. It is 
to such arguments that we shall confine our attention. 
" Natural divination," that is, predictions made under direct 
divine inspiration without interposition of signs and por- 
tents, is not magic and so the discussion of it will not con- 
cern us. Much less shall we waste any time over such trite 
contentions against divination in general as that there is no 
use of knowing predetermined events since you cannot avoid 
them,^ and that even if we can learn the future we shall be 
happier not to do it. 

are to be subjected to tihe stars, then inanimate diings must be too, 
than which nothing could be more absurd. 

" Illud autem condonare se iis dicebat, quod non id quoque requireret, 
si vitae mortisque hominum rerumque humanarum omnium tempus et 
ratio et causa in coelo et apud Stellas foret, quid de muscis aut vermi- 
culis aut echinis, multisque aliis minutissimis terra marique animantibus, 
diicerent? An ista quoque isdem, quibus homines, legibus nascerentur, 
isdemque itidem exstinguerentur." Aulus Gellius, Nodes Atticae, bk. 
xiv, ch. I, sect. 12. 

" Et si ad rem pertinet, quo modo coelo affecto compositisque sideri- 
bus quodque animal oriatur; valeat id necesse est etiam in rebus 
inanimis. Quo quid dici potest absurdius ?" De Divin., bk. ii, ch. 47. 

Favorinus, however, does hint in one place that the sole evidence 
that we possess of any influence of the stars upon us is a few such 
causal connections as that between the phases of the moon and the 
tides of the ocean. 

1 Ptolemy made a fair retort to this argument by holding that fore- 
knowledge, even if it could not enable us to avoid the coming event, at 
least served the purpose o^ breaking the news gently and saving us the 
more vivid shock which the actual event, if unexpected, would cause 
by its raw reality. 



94 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [94 

De Divinatione takes the form of a suppositious conver- 
sation, or better, informal debate, between the author and 
his brother Quintus. In the first book Quintus, in a rather 
rambhng and leisurely fashion, and with occasional repe- 
tition of ideas, upholds divination to the best of his ability, 
citing many reported instances of successful recourse to it 
in antiquity. In the second book Tully proceeds, with an 
air of somewhat patronizing superiority, to pull entirely to 
pieces the arguments of his brother, who assents with cheer- 
ful readiness to their demolition. 

It is interesting to note that as Pliny's magic was not his 
own, so Cicero's scepticism did not originate wholly with 
himself. As his other philosophical writings draw their 
material largely from Greek philosophy, so the second book 
of the De Divinatione is supposed to have been under con- 
siderable obligations to Clitomachus and Panaetius.^ As 
for the future, the De Divinatione was known in the Middle 
Ages but its influence seems to have often been scarcely that 
intended by its author. 

One of the main points in the argument of Quintus had 
been his appeal to the past. What race or state, he asked, 
has not believed in some form of divination? 

For before the revelation of philosophy, which was discovered 
recently, public opinion had no doubt of the truth of this art ; 
and after philosophy came forth no philosopher of authority 
thought otherwise. I have mentioned Pythagoras, Democritus, 
Socrates. I have left out no one of the ancients save Xeno- 
phanes. I have added the Old Academy, the Peripatetics, the 
Stoics. Epicurus alone dissented.^ 

^ See T. Schiohe, De Fontibus Lihrorum Ciceronis qui sunt de 
Divinatione, (Jena, 1875) and K. Hartfelder, Die Quellen von Ciceros 
zwei BUchern de Divinatione (Freiburg, 1878). 

2 Bk. i, ch. 39. " Neque ante philosophiam patefactam, quae nuper 



95] CRITICS OF MAGIC 95 

When TuUy's turn to speak came, he rudely disturbed 
his brother's reliance upon tradition. " I think it not the 
part of a philosopher to employ witnesses, who are only 
haply true, often purposely false and deceiving. He ought 
to show why a thing is so by arguments and reasons, not 
by events, especially those I cannot credit." ^ "Antiquity," 
Cicero declared later, " has erred in many respects." ^ The 
existence of the art of divination in every age and nation 
had little effect upon him. There is nothing, he asserted, so 
widespread as ignorance.* 

Both brothers distinguished divination from the natural 
sciences and assigned it a place by itself.* Quintus said that 
medical men, pilots and farmers foresee many things, yet 
their arts are not divination. " Not even Pherecydes, that 
famous Pythagorean master, who prophesied an earthquake 
when he saw there was no water in a well usually full, 
should be regarded as a diviner rather than a physicist." ^ 
In like manner Tully pointed out that the sick seek a doctor, 
not a soothsayer, that diviners cannot instruct us in astron- 

inventa est, hac de re communis vita du'bitavit ; et postea, quam pihilosa- 
phia processit, nemo aliter philosophus sensit, in quo modo esset auc- 
toritas. Dixi de P3rthagora, de Demoorite, de Socrate; excepi de anti- 
quis praeter Xenophanem neminem; adiunxi veterem academiam, peri- 
pateticos, stoicos. Unus dissentit Epicurus." This trust in tradition, it 
may ibe here observed, formed one of the chief grounds for mediaeval 
belief in magic as well. 

^ Bk. ii, ch. II. "Hoc ego philosophi non arbitror, testibus uti, qui 
aut casu veri aut malitia falsi fictique esse possunt. Argumentis et 
rationibus oportet quare quidque ita sit docere, non eventis, iis praeser- 
tim quibus mihi liceat non credere." 

2 Bk. ii, ch. 33. " Errabat enim multis in rebus antiquitas." 

» Bk. ii, ch. 36. 

* As Tully (bk. ii, ch. 5) puts it, " Quae enim praesentiri aut arte 
aut ratione aut usu aut oonjectura possunt, ea non divinis tribuenda 
putas sed peritis." 

5 Bk. i, ch. 50. 



gg MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [96 

omy, that no one consults them- concerning philosophic 
problems or ethical questions, that they can give us no light 
on the problems of the natural universe, and that they are 
of no service in logic, dialectic or political science.^ Such 
would be the ideal condition, but in practice, as we have 
seen much reason to believe, divination, at least in the broad 
sense, was confused with science and with other subjects to 
no small extent both under the Empire and in the Middle 
Ages. A doctor might be something of a diviner as well : the 
astrologer was skilled in astronomy; "mathematicus" came 
within a short time after Cicero's own day to be the word 
regularly used to denote a soothsayer ; ^ Pierre du Bois and 
Bodin found astrology an aid to political science. 

Cicero, however, went further than the assertion that 
divination had no connection with science and declared that 
it was contrary to science. Such a figment, he scornfully 
affirmed, as that the heart will vanish from a corpse for one 
man's benefit and remain in the body to suit the future of 
another, was not believed even by old wives now-a-days.' 
Nay more, he asked, how can the heart vanish from- the 
body? Surely it must be there while life lasts, and can it 
disappear in an instant? 

Believe me, you are abandoning the citadel of philosophy 
while you defend its outposts. For in your effort to prove 
soothsaying true you utterly pervert physiology. . . . For there 
will be something which either springs from nothing or sud- 
denly vanishes into nothingness. What scientist ever said that ? 
The soothsayers say so? Are they then, do you think, to 
be trusted rather than scientists ? * 

Cicero does not think they are. 

^ Bk. ii, chs. 3, 4. 

2 We saw Pliny use " mathematicae artes " as an equivalent of 
divination or astrology. 

^ Bk. ii, ch. 15. 

* Bk. ii, ch. 16. " Urbem phiiosophiae, mihi crede, proditis dum 



97] CRITICS OF MAGIC 97 

Also he shows that the methods of divination are not 
scientific. He asks: Why did Calchas deduce from the 
devoured sparrow that the Trojan war would last ten years 
rather than ten weeks or ten months ? ^ He points out that 
the art is conducted in different places according to quite 
different rules of procedure, even to the extent that a favor- 
able omen in one locality is a sinister warning elsewhere.* 
In short, whether he got his idea from the Greeks or not, 
he has come, long before most men had reached that point, 
to have a clear idea of the essential contradiction between 
science and magic. " Quid igitur," he asks, " minus a 
physicis dici debet quam quidquam certi significari rebus 
incertis ?" * 

Besides this sharp separation of divination from science 
and besides his rejection of tradition, a third creditable 
feature of Cicero's book is his question: What intimate 
connection, what bond of natural causality can there be be- 
tween the liver or heart or lung of a fat bull and the divine 
eternal cause of things which rules the world ? * He re- 
fuses to believe in any extraordinary bonds of sympathy 
between things which, in so far as our daily experience and 

castella defenditis. Nam dum aruspicinam veram esse vultis, pihy- 
siologiam totam pervertitis. Caput est in jecore, cor in extis: iam ab- 
scedet, simul ac molam et vinum insperseris; deus id eripiet, vis aliqua 
conficiet, aut exedet Non ergo omnium anteritus atque obitus natura 
coniiciet ; et erit aliquid quod aut ex nihilo oriatur, aut in nihilum subito 
occidat. Quis hoc physicus dixit unquam ? Aruspices dicunt ? His 
igitur quam physicis potius credendum existimas?" 

1 Bk. ii, ch. 28. 2 Bk. ii, ch. 12. « Bk. ii, ch. 19. 

* Bk ii, dh. 12. "Atqui divina cum rerum natura tanta tamquo 
praeclara in omnes partes motusque diffusa, quid habere potest com- 
mune, non dicam gallinacum fel (sunt enim qui vel argutissima haec 
exta esse dicant) sed tauri opimi jecur aut cor aut pulmo, quid habet 
naturale, quo deolarari possit quid futurum sit?" 



gg MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [98 

our knowledge of nature's workings can inform us, have 
absolutely no connection. He appeals to the canons of 
common sense. In fact, it is generally true throughout his 
treatise that where he cannot disprove, he pooh-poohs super- 
stition. 

On the whole Cicero's attitude probably represents the 
most enlightened scepticism to be found in the ancient world. 
Though some of his arguments seem weak, he deserves 
credit for having argued at all. Against what they were 
pleased to call magic, men, especially during the Middle 
Ages, were apt to rant rather than reason. 

But, alas, unless we assume that the famous Dream of 
Scipio is a purely imaginative production, that the fantastic 
beliefs there set forth (borrowed, no doubt, from Gredc 
thought) are presented for dramatic purposes alone and do 
not represent Cicero's actual views, we must grant that our 
scq)tical Cicero believed in some magic after all. For the 
Drcmn, despite its author's animadversions against Chal- 
daeaii astrology, speaks of Jupiter as a star wholesome and 
favorable to the human race, of Mars as most unfavorable.^ 
Also it calls the numbers seven and eight perfect and speaks 
of their product as signifying the fatal year in Scipio's 
career.' 

i '* Deinde est hominmn generi prospenis et salutaris ille f ulgor qui 
dicitur Jovis. Turn rutilus horribilisque terris, quern Martium dicitis. 
Deinde subter mediam fere regionem Sol obtinet^ dux et princeps et 
moderator lusninum reliquonim, mens xnundi et temperatio," etc, 

s'^Nam cum aetas tua septenos octies solis anfractus reditusque 
asverterit, duoque fai numeri, quorum uterque plenus, alter altera de 
lidietnr, ciicuitu natural! summam tibi fatalem confecerint, etcP 



CHAPTER VII 

The Last Century of the Empire 

We come now to consider some indications of the inter- 
mixture of magic with learning in the last century of the 
Roman Empire, the border-time of the Middle Ages. It 
was a time when interest in science was slight and when 
the ability to use florid rhetoric was apparently the chief 
aim of those who assumed to be the highest intellectual 
class. What science there was was largely permeated with 
magic, as a glance at a few men of intellectual prominence 
then will illustrate. I 

Marcellus of Bordeaux, court physician of Theodosius I, 
and a writer upon medicine, throws some light upon the 
state of medicine in his day. He affirmed that pimples 
might be removed by wiping them the instant you saw a 
falling-star. He said that a tumor could be cured if one 
half of a root of vervain were tied about the sufferer's neck 
and the other half suspended over a fire. His theory was 
that as the vervain dried up in the smoke of the fire, the 
tumor would by force of magic sympathy likewise dry up 
and disappear. Marcellus added for the benefit of unpaid 
physicians that so persistent would be the sympathetic bond 
established that if the root of the vervain were later thrown 
into water, its absorption of moisture would produce a re- 
turn of the tumor. ^ 

Ammianus Marcellinus, who wrote at the close of the 

1 These recipes are given in Frazer*s Golden Bough, vol. i, p. 23, from 
the De Medicamentis of Marcellus, bk. xv, ch. 82 and bk. xxxiv, di. 100. 
99] 99 



lOO MAGIC IS ISTELLECTUAL HISTORY [loo 

foorth ccntmy, and who has been regarded by his critics 
from Gibbon down as a historian of disdi^^uished merit, 
gives OS an idea of mental conditions in his time, and was 
himsdf not free from belief in magic It is true that in de- 
claiming against the d^neneracy of the Roman aristocracy 
he ridictiles their trust in astrcrfogy, saying that many of 
them deny the existence of higher powers in heaven, yet 
diink it imprudent to Bppe^r in poblic or dine or take a bath 
without first ha\~ii^ consuked an almanac as to Merctuy's 
whereabouts or the exact position of the mocn in Cancer.^ 
Yet he believed in omens, portents and auspices, as the fol- 
lowing citations will indicate and as one might show by 
other passages. 

The first passage is one in which Ammianus speaks of 
Alexandria as formerly having been a great place of leam- 
ii^ and as e>-en in his degenerate days a considerable in- 
tellectual centre. According to him, it is a sufficient rec- 
ommendaticHi for any medical man if he say that he was 
educated at Alexandria.* 

There whatever lies hidden is laid bare by g^ecxnetry; music 

1 Ammianas Marcellinus. R^rum gestarmm Hbri qui supersMUt. F. 
Eyssenhardt recensuit. Berlin, 1871. Book xxviii, ch. iv, sec 24. 
'^ Muld apud eos negantes esse soperas potcstates in caelo, nee in publico 
prodeunt nee prandent nee lavari arbitrantor se caotins posse, anteqnam 
ephemeride scmpulose sciscitata didiceiint. nlw sit vcrbi gratia sigmun 
Mercurii, vel quotam cancri sideris partem polnm discurrens i^^dneat 
luna." Very likel>% however, .\mnuanu$ — whom we shall see defending 
divination in general — himself cherished a moderate tmst in astit^ogy 
and was rather satirizing the tntkiclity of the nobles — their incon- 
sistency in so minutely ruling their Itxt^ by the planets when Aey 
denied the existence of " su^^era^i \Hnv^sult?t m *\wfv.»." There is an Eng- 
lish translation of Ammianus by C IV YvMX^e (London, 1862; Bohn 
Library). 

* Ibid., bk. xxii, di. xy\» »ec> ^H^ *^ Fro omni tamcn experimento 
sufficiat medico ad commeiHUuvUm «rtU »uctoritatenu si .\lexandriae 
se dixerit emdittmL" 



lOi] THE LAST CENTURY OF THE EMPIRE loi 

is not utterly forgotten nor harmony neglected; among some 
men, though their number may not be great, the motion of the 
world and stars is still a matter of consideration; there are 
not a few of those skilled in numbers. 

This is not all. " Besides these things they cherish the 
science which reveals the decrees of fate." ^ 

The Emperor Julian was continually inspecting entrails 
of victims and interpreting dreams and omens, and even 
proposed to reopen a prophetic fountain which Hadrian 
was said to have blocked up for fear that others, like him- 
self, might win the imperial throne through obedience to 
its predictions.^ The mention of such practices of Julian 
leads Ammianus in another passage to attempt a justifica- 
tion of divination as a science worthy of the study and re- 
spect of the most erudite and intelligent. He says : 

Inasmuch as to this ruler, who was a man of culture and an 
inquirer into all branches of learning, malicious persons have 
attributed the use of evil arts to learn the future, we shall 
briefly indicate how a wise man is able to acquire this by no 
means trivial variety of knowledge. The spirit behind all the 
elements, seeing that it is incessantly and everywhere active 
in the prophetic movement of everlasting bodies, bestows upon 
us the gift of divination by those methods which we acquire 
through divers studies; and the forces of nature, propitiated 
by various rites, as from exhaustless springs provide mankind 
with prophetic utterances.^ 

^ Ihid.y bk. xxii, ch. xvi, sec. 17. " Et quamquam veteres cum his, 
quorum memini floruere conplures, tamen ne nunc quidem in eadem 
urbe doctrinae variae silent; nam et disciplinarum magistri quodam 
modo sipirant et nudatur ibi geometrico radio quidquid reconditum latet, 
nondumque apud eos penitus exaruit musica nee harmonica conticuit, 
et recalet apud quosdam adhuc licet raros consideratio mundani motus 
et siderum, doctique §unt numeros hau-d pauci ; super his scientiam Cal- 
ient quae factorum vias ostendit." 

2 Bk. xxii, ch. xii, sec. 8. 

» Bk. xxi, ch. i, sec. 7. " Et quoniam erudito et studioso cognitionum 












m <* ^ ^ • 



»- -. 



,• •, 



• •• • 



• • • 
••••• 



• •> '• 



* » •• • 



I02 Mi4G/C /AT INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [102 

That is, we can fordcnow, if not control, the results of the 
processes of universal nature. Since it is through the 
forces of nature that we do this, augury, oracular utter- 
ances, oneiromancy and astrology all become for Ammianus 
but subdivisions of physical science. He admits that there 
are persons who disagree with him, who object that pre- 
dictions are often erroneous; but against such persons he 
employs the old refutation that occasional mistakes are to 
be attributed to man's imperfect knowledge and faulty ol> 
servation, and that by such mistakes the validity of divina- 
tion is no more disproved than is grammar forever discred- 
ited because a grammarian speaks incorrectly, or music 
because a musician sings out of tune.^ Opposition to the 
arts of divination he calls "vanities plebeia," and upon such 
loud-mouthed ignorance of the vulgar he looks down 
with much the same superior smile that the lover of specu- 
lative philosophy to-day bestows upon the man in the street 
who irritably disputes the utility of that subject. 

Indeed, the strength of Ammianus's attachment to divi- 
nation is so great that he quotes its arch-opponent, Cicero, 
in its support. For he concludes his discussion of the sub- 
ject in these words : " Wherefore in this as in other matters 
Tully says most admirably, * Sig^s of future events are 
shown by the gods.' " * Unless perchance Ammianus was 

omnium principi malivoli praenoscendi futura pravas artes adsignant, 
advertendum est breviter imde sapienti viro hoc quoque accidere potent 
doctrinae genus haud leve, Elementorum omnium spiritus, utpote 
perennium corporum praesentendi motu semper et ubique vigens ex his 
quae per disciplinas varias affectamus, participat nobiscum munera 
divinandi; et substantiales potestates ritu diverso placatae, velut ex 
perpetviis fontium venis vaticina mortalitati subpeditant verba." 

^ Bk. xxi, ch. i, sec 13. 

2 Bk. xxi, ch. i, sec. 14. " Unde praeclare hoc quoque ut alia Tullius 
' signa ostenduntur ' ait * a dis rerum futurarum.' " " Dis " seem to be 
practically identical in Ammianus's mind with natural forces. 



I03] THE LAST CENTURY OF THE EMPIRE 103 

acquainted with the first book only of De Dwinatione, this 
remark — which ought to have proved more potent than any 
necromantic spell in invoking Cicero's slandered Manes — 
must be taken as a startling revelation of the mental calibre 
of both its maker and his age. 

Synesius (370-430 a. d.), Bishop of Ptolemais, furnishes 
a good example of what was probably the position of the 
average Neo-Platonist who did not go to extremes in the 
last period of the Roman Empire. In the present survey 
we are not concerned with Christian belief in the Empire, 
and so it is only as a Neo-Platonist that Synesius will at 
present interest us. He is the more interesting for us in 
that he was a man with some taste for science. He knew 
some medicine and was well acquainted with geometry and 
astronomy, subjects which he probably studied under his 
friend Hypatia. He believed himself to be the inventor 
of an astrolable and of a hydroscope. He played his 
part in secular politics and as bishop defended his peo- 
ple from oppression. He was fond of the chase and 
of his dogs and horses, and said so. He was a great 
lover of books also, but thought that their true use 
was to call one's own mental powers into action. Phil- 
osophy, mathematics and literature all claimed his attention. 
Yet broad and independent-minded as he was for his age, 
and interested as he was in science, he believed in magic. 
Indeed, there was apparently no form of magic in which 
he would not have believed. 

Synesius regarded the universe as a upit and all its parts 
as closely correlated. This belief not only led him to main- 
tain, like Seneca, that whatever had a cause was a sign of 
some future event, or to hold with Plotinus that in any 
and every object the sage might discern the future of every 
other thing, and that the birds themselves, if endowed with 
sufficient intelligence, would be able to predict the future by 



I04 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [104 

observing the movements of human bipeds.^ It led him 
also to the conclusion that the various parts of the universe 
were more than passive mirrors in which one might see 
the future of the other parts ; that they further exerted, by 
virtue of the magic sympathy which united all parts of the 
universe, a potent active influence over other objects and 
occurrences. The wise man might not only predict the 
future; he might, to a great extent, control it. 

For it must be, I think, that of this whole, so joined in sym- 
pathy and in agreement, the parts are closely connected as if 
members of a single body. And does not this explain the 
spells of the magi? For things, besides being signs of each 
other, have magic power over each other. The wise man, then, 
is he who knows the relationships of the parts of the universe. 
For he draws one object under his control by means of another 
object, holding what is at hand as a pledge for what is far 
away, and working through sounds and material substances 
and forms.^ 

Synesius explained that plants and stones are related by 

^TLeplhwrviuv. (On Dreams) ch. 2. Synesii Cyrendei Quae Extant 
Opera Omnia, lo. Georgius Krabinger. Landishuti, mdcccl. Tomus 
I.) All following references to and quotations from the works of 
Synesius apply to this edition. There is a French translation with 
several introductory essays by H. Druon, Paris, 1878. For an account 
in English of Synesius and his writings see W. S. Crawford, Synesius 
the Hellene, London, 1901. See also, H. O. Taylor, Classical Heritage 
of the Middle Ages, pp. 78-82, New York, 1901. This interesting work 
gives illustrations in various fields of the continuity of culture during 
the transition from Roman times to the Middle Ages. 

^Uspl kinjirviijv [On Dreams) ch. 3. 'Ede* ydp, olimi^ Tov iravrdg tovtov 
avjiiradovg re dvrog Kal avfiirvov ra fjiprj irpoa^KELV ak\ip\jOLq^ are evbg 6Aov rd fiiTnj 
Tvyx^vovra, Kal fiij irore al fidycjv Ivyyeg avTai- Kal yap di2,yeTai trap a?JJf7uuv^ 
Ctairep arffiaiveTai' Kal ao(l>bg 6 eldag rrjv tuv fiepcjv tov Kdofiov avyytveiav, 'E/l/cei 
yap IlTOm 61 oTJMVy ix^^ evexvpa irapdwa rav irTieltTTOv dirdvrcjv^ Kal ^(jvdg, Kal 

i^ag Kal ax^fiara Evidently Synesius did not regard the magi as 

mere imposters. 



I05] THE LAST CENTURY OF THE EMPIRE 105 

bonds of occult sympathy to the gods who are within the 
universe and who form a part of it, that plants and stones 
have magic power over these gods, and that one may by 
means of such material substances attract those deities.^ 
He evidently believed that it was quite legitimate to control 
the processes of nature by invoking demons. His devotion 
to divination has been already implied. He regarded it as 
among the noblest of human pursuits.^ Dreams he viewed 
as significant and very useful events. They aided him, he 
wrote, in his every-day life, and had upon one occasion 
saved him from magic devices against his life.* Of course, 
he had faith in aerology. The stars were wdl-nigh ever 
present in his thought. In his Praise of Baldness he char- 
acterized comets as fatal omens, as harbingers of the worst 
public disasters.* In On Providence he explained the sup- 
posed fact that history repeats itself by the periodical re- 
turn to their former positions of the stars which govern 
our life.*^ In On the Gift of an Astrolabe he declared that 
" astronomy " besides being itself a noble science, prepared 
men for the diviner mysteries of theology.* Finally, he 
held the view common among students of magic that knowl- 
edge should be esoteric; that its mysteries and marvels 
should be confined to the few fitted to receive them and that 
they should be expressed in language incomprehensible to 
the vulgar crowd. "^ 

^Tlepl eWTTvicoVf ch. 3. Kal drj Koi de(p rivl tgw elatj rob Kdofwv ?iidog kvdMe 
Kol pordvTj irpoa^KEij olg d^oioTraOov eIkel ry (phaet koI yorfTeverai, In his Praise 
of Baldness {^aXdKpag kyK^fiLov), ch. 10, Synesius tells how the Egyptians 
attract demons by magic influences. 

' Uspi kwKviuv^ ch. I. Avrat fi^v airodel^eig karuw tov fMvreiav h roig dpioroic 
elvai TGJv hiTLTrjdevoiitvQv avOp/jiroig. 

*Ibid,y ch. 18. *^aXdKpac kyiUjfiiov, ch. 10. 

^ AlyiiTTioi ^ irepl Trpovoiag, bk. ii, ch. 7. 

•npdf iraidvwv ire pi tov 66pov^ ch. 5. 

^Atwv, ch. 7. U.£pi kwTTviuVy ch. 4. 'ETTttrroAat, 4 and 49. 




Io6 MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [io6 

Macrobius, who wrote at the beginning of the fifth cen- 
tury and displayed considerable interest in physical ques- 
tions for a person of those days, reinforces the evidence of 
Ammianus and of Synesius, although he held no very ex- 
treme views. Unless, however, we except his Philonian 
notion that all knowledge may be derived from a few past 
writings. For Macrobius affirmed that Virgil contains 
practically all man needs to know, and that Cicero's brief 
story of the dream of Scipio was a work second to none 
and contained the entire substance of philosophy.^ Macro- 
bius also believed that numbers possess occult power. He 
dilated at considerable length upon each of those from one 
to eight, emphasizing their perfection and far-reaching sig- 
nificance. He held the good old P3rthagorean and Platonic 
notions that the world-soul is constructed of number, that 
the harmony of celestial bodies is ruled by number, and that 
we derive the numerical values proper to musical conson- 
ance from the music of the spheres.^ He was of the opin- 
ion that to the careful investigator dreams and other strik- 
ing occurrences will reveal an occult meaning.' As for 
astrology, he believed that the stars are signs but not causes 
of future events, just as birds by their flight or song reveal 
matters of which they themselves are ignorant.* The sun 
and planets, though in a way divine, are but material bodies, 
and it is not from them but from the world-soul (pure 
mind), whence they too come, that the human spirit takes 

1 " Universa philosophiae integrita-s." Commentary on Dream of 
Scipio, bk. ii, ch. 17. For Macrobius on Virgil see T. R. Glover, Lif& 
and Letters in the Fourth Century a. d. (Cambridge, Eng., 1901), p. 181, 
and Macrobius, Saturnaliay bk. a, ch. xvi, sec. 12. Macrobius has been 
edited in French and Latin by Nisard. Paris, 1883. 

2 Commentary, bk. i, chs. 5 and 6 ; ii, ch. i and 2. 

8 Ihid., bk. i, ch. 7. 

* Ihid.y bk. i, ch. 19. 



p7] CRITICS OF MAGIC 97 

Also he shows that the methods of divination are not 
scientific. He asks: Why did Calchas deduce from the 
devoured sparrow that the Trojan war would last ten years 
rather than ten weeks or ten months ? ^ He points out that 
the art is conducted in different places according to quite 
different rules of procedure, even to the extent that a favor- 
able omen in one locality is a sinister warning elsewhere.* 
In short, whether he got his idea from the Greeks or not, 
he has come, long before most men had reached that point, 
to have a clear idea of the essential contradiction between 
science and magic. " Quid igitur," he asks, " minus a 
physicis dici debet quam quidquam certi significari rebus 
incertis ?" * 

Besides this sharp separation of divination from science 
and besides his rejection of tradition, a third creditable 
feature of Cicero's book is his question: What intimate 
connection, what bond of natural causality can there be be- 
tween the liver or heart or lung of a fat bull and the divine 
eternal cause of things which rules the world ? * He re- 
fuses to believe in any extraordinary bonds of sympathy 
between things which, in so far as our daily experience and 

castella -defenditis. Nam dum aruspicinam veram esse vultis, pihy- 
siologiam totam pervertitis. Caput est in jecore, cor in extis: iam ab- 
scedet, simul ac molam et vinum insperseris ; deus id eripiet, vis aliqua 
conficiet, aut exedet Non ergo omnium interitus atque obitus natura 
conficiet ; et erh aliquid quod aut ex nihilo oriatur, aut in nihilum subito 
occidat. Quis hoc physicus dixit unquam? Aruspices dicunt? His 
igitur quam physicis potius credendum existimas?" 

1 Bk. ii, ch. 28. 2 Bk. ii, ch. 12. s sk. ii, ch. 19. 

* Bk. ii, <fli. 12. "Atqui divina cum rerum natura tanta tamque 
praeclara in omnes partes motusque diffusa, quid habere potest com- 
mune, non dicam gallinacum fel (sunt enim qui vel argutissima haec 
exta esse dicant) sed tauri opimi jecur aut cor aut pulmo, quid habet 
naturale, quo deolarari possit quid futurum sit?" 



CHAPTER VIII 



Conclusion 



Our survey of the Roman Empire and of the ancient 
world of thought which it represented is finished. We have 
found reason to beheve that hatred and dread of " magic," 
the confusion of science or of philosophy with magic, 
the incurring of reputations as wizards by men of learn- 
ing, were phenomena not confined to the Middle Ages. 
We have seen some evidence of the prominence of magic 
in the intellectual life of the Roman Empire, in the writings 
and in the conduct of physicians and astronomers, of states- 
men and philosophers. Just how prominent magic was one 
hesitates to estimate, but one may safely affirm that it was 
sufficiently prominent to merit the attention of the student 
of those times. It is almost useless to chronicle the events 
if we do not understand the spirit of an age. 

Can the student of that age, we may ask in conclud- 
ing, rightly interpret and appreciate it, can he make 
proper use of its extant records, unless he recognizes 
not merely that men made mistakes then and accepted a 
mass of false statements concerning nature, but that the 
best minds were liable to be esoteric and mystical, to incline 
to the occult and the fantastic, to be befogged by absurd 
credulity and by great mental confusion, to be fettered by 
habits of childish and romantic reasoning such as occurs 
in Ptolemy's Tetrabiblos and in Plato's Timaeus? Have 
we a right * to attribute to the minds of that age our 

definiteness and clarity of thought, our common sense, our 
io8 [io8 



I09] CONCLUSION 109 

scientific spirit? Is it fair to take the words in which they 
expressed their thought and to interpret these according to 
our knowledge, our frame of mind ; to read into their words 
our ideas and discoveries; to rearrange their disconnected 
utterances into systems which they were incapable of con- 
structing; to endeavor by nothing else than a sort of alle- 
gorical interpretation to discover our philosophy, our 
science, our ideals in their writings ? Have not even words 
a greater definiteness and value now than once? When we 
translate a passage from an ancient language are we not apt 
to transfigure its thought ? These are, however, only ques- 
tions. 

Certainly there was much true scientific knowledge in the 
Roman Empire. There was sane medical theory and prac- 
tice, there was a great deal of correct information in regard 
to plants, animals and the stars. Science was in the ascen- 
dant; magic was in its latter stages of decay. We flatter 
ourselves that it has now quite vanished away; then its doc- 
trines were accepted only in part or in weakened form by 
men of education. Perhaps, though I am far from assert- 
ing this, magic played a less prominent part then in science 
and in philosophy than in the later Middle Ages. Perhaps 
we may picture to ourselves the minds of men in the twelfth 
and thirteenth and succeeding centuries as awakening from 
a long, intellectual torpor during the chaotic and dreary 
" Dark Ages," and, eager for knowledge and for mental 
occupation, but still inexperienced and rather bewildered, 
as snatching without discrimination at whatever came first 
to hand of the lore of the past. Thus for a time we might 
find the most able men of the later age taking on the worst 
characteristics of the earlier time. But this again is mere 
speculation. 

Moreover, we must remember that, if magic was accepted 
only in part by men of learning in the Roman Empire, there 



I lO MAGIC IN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY [no 

was no thoroughgoing scepticism. We sought in vain 
for an instance of consistent disbelief. If, too, there 
was an effort to make the magic, which was accepted, scien- 
tific by basing it upon natural laws, as Quintus Cicero, 
Seneca and Ptolemy tried to do, there was also, besides the 
definite approval of magical doctrines, often a mys- 
tical tone in the science and philosophy of the time. The 
question of the relative strength of magic and of science in 
those days must, then, be left unsettled. It is difficult 
enough to judge even a single individual; to tell, for in- 
stance, just how superstitious Cato was. 

In closing we may, however, sum up very briefly those 
elements which we selected as combining to give a fairly 
faithful picture of the belief in magic which then pre- 
vailed among educated people. Native superstitions from 
which science had not yet wholly freed itself; much 
fantastical and mystical lore from Oriental nations; 
allegorizing and mysticizing in the interpretation of 
books — which in Philo went to the length of a be- 
lief that all knowledge could be secured by this means; 
a portrayal of nature which attributed to her many magic 
properties and caused medicine to be infected with magic 
ceremony and to be based to some extent on the principle 
of sympathetic magic ; a widespread and often extreme belief 
in astrology; a speculative philosophy which was often 
favorable to the doctrines of magic or even advanced some 
itself; and the system of Neo-Platonism in especial, with 
which we may associate the view — ^prevalent long before 
Plotinus, however — ^that everything in the universe is in 
close s)mipathy with everything else and is a sign of com- 
ing events — these were the forces ready at the opening of 
the Middle Ages to influence the future. 



VITA 

Lynn Thorndike, the writer of this dissertation, was 
bom in July, 1882, at Lynn, Massachusetts. In 1902 he 
received the A. B. degree from Wesleyan University, Con- 
necticut, and in 1903 he obtained the A. M. degree from 
Columbia University. He was in residence at Columbia 
during the three years from 1902- 1903 to 1904- 1905. In 
these years he attended lectures on Comparative Jurispru- 
dence by Professor Munroe-Smith, lectures on American 
Colonial History and on English History by Professor 
Osgood, and lectures on European History by Professors 
Robinson and Sloane. He was a member of Professor 
Robinson's Seminar in Later Mediaeval and Modem His- 
tory, and of Professor Sloane's Seminar on the work of 
Napoleon. In 1902- 1903 and 1903- 1904 he was a Univer- 
sity Scholar in European History; in 1904-5 he was Uni- 
versity Fellow in European History. He is a member of 

the Phi Beta Kappa Society. 

Ill 









1 
J 

i 


STANFORD UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES 

STANFORD AUXILIARY LIBRARY 

STANFORD, CALIFORNIA 94305-6004 

(4151 723-9201 

All books may be recalled offer 7 days 

DATE DUE 


28D ^"41^4 




■■■■BSr ^^S_ 


~ 


•^